The New Spirituality
and the Christ Experience of the Twentieth Century
GA 200
17 October 1920, Dornach
Lecture I
In the lectures given here during the course on history1 These were the lectures given by Dr Karl Heyer on 14, 15 and 16 October 1920, during the first course of the School of Anthroposophy at the Goetheanum with the theme: 'The Science of History and History from the Viewpoint of Anthroposophy' ('Anthroposophische Betrachtungen Ober die Geschichtswissenschaft und aus der Geschichte'). These are printed in Kultur und Erziehung (the third volume of the Courses of the School of Anthroposophy), Stuttgart, 1921. several things were mentioned which, particularly at the present time, it is especially important to consider. With regard to the historical course of humanity's development, the much-debated question mentioned to begin with was whether the outstanding and leading individual personalities are the principal driving forces in this development or whether the most important things are brought about by the masses. In many circles this has always been a point of contention and the conclusions have been drawn, more from sympathy and antipathy than from real knowledge. This is one fact which, in a certain sense, I should like to mention as being very important.
Another fact which, from a look at history, I should like to mention for its importance is the following. At the beginning of the nineteenth century Wilhelm von Humboldt2 See Wilhelm von Humboldt (1767–1835): Über die Aufgabe des Geschiclztsschreibens (The Task of the Historian) in Volume IV of Humboldt's Works published by Leitzman, Berlin 1905 (see pages 35-56). Some relevant passages taken from these are as follows:
"The business of the historian, in the last but simplest analysis, is to portray the striving of an idea to attain existence in reality. For it is not always that it succeeds in this at the first attempt; and it is not so rare that the idea degenerates because it is unable to master in a pure way the matter counteracting it."
"The truth of everything that happens lies in the addition of the above-mentioned invisible part of every fact, and thus the history writer must add this to the events. Seen from this angle he is self-acting and even creative—not, indeed, by producing what does not already exist, but by forming out of his own inner strength that which, as it is in reality, he could not perceive through mere receptivity. In different ways, but just like the poet, he must in himself transform the scattered fragments into a whole."
"It may seem dubious to allow the realm of the history writer and that of the poet to meet, even at only one point. But the activity of both is undeniably related. For if the historian, like the poet, can achieve truth in his presentation of past events only by completing and linking the incomplete and disjointed elements of direct observation, then he does so, like the poet, only through imagination. Because, however, he places imagination subordinate to experience and the fathoming of reality, there is a difference here which cancels out all danger. Imagination does not work, at this lower position, as pure imagination, and is therefore more properly called an intuitive faculty and a talent for finding links."
"Of necessity, therefore, the historian too, must strive; not, like the poet, to give his material over to the dominion of the form of necessity but to hold steadily in consciousness the ideas which are its laws, because, permeated only by, these, he can then find their trace in the pure research of the real in its reality."
"The historian encompasses all the threads of earthly activity and all varieties of supersensible ideas; the sum-total of existence, more or less, is the object of his work and he must therefore also follow all avenues of the mind and spirit. Speculation, experience and poetry, however, are not separate, opposed and mutually-limiting activities of the mind, but different planes of its radiance."
"Apart from the fact that history, like every scientific activity, serves many subsidiary purposes, work on history is no less a free art, complete in itself, than philosophy and poetry."
"Just as philosophy strives for the first foundation of things, and art for the ideal of beauty, so history strives for a picture of human destiny in faithful truth, living abundance and pure clarity that are perceived by the warm inner-being [of the historian] in such a way that his personal views, feelings and demands are lost and dissolved away. It is the final purpose of the history-writer to awaken and nourish this mood, which, however, he only attains when he pursues for his fellow human beings the simple presentation of past events with conscientious faithfulness." appeared with a definite declaration, stipulating that history should be treated in such a way that one would not only consider the individual facts which can be outwardly observed in the physical world but, out of an encompassing, synthesizing force, would see what is at work in the unfolding of history—which can only be found by someone who knows how to get a total view of the facts in what in a sense is a poetic way, but in fact produces a true picture. Attention was also drawn to how in the course of the nineteenth century it was precisely the opposite historical mode of thought and approach which was then particularly developed, and that it was not the ideas in history that were pursued but only a sense that was developed for the external world of facts. Attention was also drawn to the fact that, with regard to this last question, one can only come to clarity through spiritual science, because spiritual science alone can uncover the real driving forces of the historical evolution of humanity.
A spiritual science of this kind was not yet accessible to Humboldt. He spoke of ideas, but ideas indeed have no driving force [of their own]. Ideas as such are abstractions, as I mentioned here yesterday3 See the final words of Rudolf Steiner, on 16 October 1920, after the close of the first course of the Anthroposophical School, in Die Kunst der Rezitation and Deklamation (First Edition) Dornach, 1928, page 118. And anyone who might wish to find ideas as the driving forces of history would never be able to prove that ideas really do anything because they are nothing of real substantiality, and only something of substantiality can do something. Spiritual science points to real spiritual forces that are behind the sensible-physical facts, and it is in real spiritual forces such as these that the propelling forces of history lie, even though these spiritual forces will have to be expressed for human beings through ideas.
But we come to clarity concerning these things only when, from a spiritual-scientific standpoint, we look more deeply into the historical development of humanity and we will do so today in such a way that, through our considerations, certain facts come to us which, precisely for a discerning judgement of the situation of modern humanity, will prove to be of importance.
I have often mentioned4 See i>Geschictliche Symptomatologie (GA 185), nine lectures given in Dornach in 1918, only two of which are translated in From Symptom to Reality in Modern History. that spiritual science, if it looks at history, would actually have to pursue a symptomatology; a symptomatology constituted from the fact that one is aware that behind what takes it course as the stream of physical-sensible facts lie the driving spiritual forces. But everywhere in historical development there are times when what has real being and essence (das eigentlich Wesenhafte) comes as a symptom to the surface and can be judged discerningly from the phenomena only if one has the possibility to penetrate more deeply from one's awareness of these phenomena into the depths of historical development.
I would like to clarify this by a simple diagram. Let us suppose that this is a flow of historical facts (see diagram). The driving forces lie, for ordinary observation, below the flow of these facts. And if the eye of the soul observes the flow in this way, then the real activity of the driving forces would lie beneath it (red). But there are significant points in this flow of facts. And these significant points are distinguished by the fact that what is otherwise hidden comes here to the surface. Thus we can say: Here, in a particular phenomenon, which must only be properly evaluated, it was possible to become aware of something which otherwise is at work everywhere, but which does not show itself in such a significant manifestation.

Let us assume that this (see diagram) took place in some year of world history, let us say around 800 A.D. What was significant for Europe, let us say for Western Europe, was of course at work before this and worked on afterwards, but it did not manifest itself in such a significant way in the time before and after as it did here. If one points to a way of looking at history like this, a way which looks to significant moments, such a method would be in complete accord with Goetheanism. For Goethe wished in general that all perception of the world should be directed to significant points and then, from what could be seen from such points, the remaining content of world events be recognized. Goethe says of this5 See Bedeutende Fordnis durch ein einziges geistreiches Wort in Goethes Naturwissenschaftliche Schriften, edited and with a commentary by Rudolf Steiner in Kürschner's Deutsche National-Literatur, Volume II, page 34 (GA lb). Goethe says here:
"I do not rest until I find a significant point from which a great deal can be deduced or, rather, which of its own will brings forth a great deal and presents this to me, and which I then, with attention and receptivity, work on further faithfully and carefully. If, in my experience, I find some phenomenon which I cannot deduce, I simply let it lie as a problem; and I have found, in my long life, this way of doing things to be very beneficial. For when I was not able for a long time to unravel the origin or connection of some phenomenon but had to put it to one side, I found that, years later, it all suddenly became clear in the most beautiful way." that, within the abundance of facts, the important thing is to find a significant point from which the neighbouring areas can be viewed and from which much can be deciphered.
So let us take this year 800 A.D. We can point here to a fact in the history of Western European humanity which, from the point of view of the usual approach to history, might seem insignificant—which one would perhaps not find worthy of attention for what is usually called history—but which, nevertheless, for a deeper view of humanity's development, is indeed significant. Around this year there was a kind of learned theological argument between the man who was a sort of court philosopher of the Frankish realm, Alcuin,6 Alcuin (also Alhuin or Alchwin, i.e. 'Friend of the Temple') was rector of the monastery school at York around 735 to 804. In 782 he followed the summons of Charlemagne and took on the headship of the court school. He encouraged the sciences in the monasteries and raised to the central seat of the sciences the monastery school of St Martin at Tours, which he founded and whose Abbot he became in 796.
The debate with the Greek is described in Karl Werner's book Alcuin and sein Jahrhundert (Alcuin and His Century) Vienna 1881, Chapter 11. page 166, as follows:
Thus Charlemagne once wanted to know from Alcuin what should be made of the view of a Greek scholar, who presumably was a member of a Byzantine legation at Charlemagne's court, who had expressed the opinion to the emperor that Christ had paid the expiation for our sins to death. Alcuin found this manner of expression and the idea behind it to be inadmissible, for Christ was not—death's debtor and could not become so—the price of our redemption was paid by Christ to our divine Father, to whom, in dying, He commended His soul. Death [so Alcuin argued] is in no way a reality of being and substance but, to his way of thinking, was something purely negative, the mere absence or 'Carence' (Church Latin: the interval before benefits become available) of life; it is nothing existing in itself, and thus cannot receive anything, no payment can be paid to it. On the contrary, in the person of Christ, death itself, which God did not create, became the ransom for our debt and won life for us thereby, which He Himself gives us in His saviour power.' and a Greek also living at that time in the kingdom of the Franks. The Greek, who was naturally at home in the particular soul-constitution of the Greek peoples which he had inherited, had wanted to reach a discerning judgement of the principles of Christianity and had come to the concept of redemption. He put the question: To whom, in the redemption through Christ Jesus, was the ransom actually paid? He, the Greek thinker, came to the solution that the ransom had been paid to Death. Thus, in a certain sense, it was a sort of redemption theory that this Greek developed from his thoroughly Greek mode of thinking, which was now just becoming acquainted with Christianity. The ransom was paid to Death by the cosmic powers.
Alcuin, who stood at that time in that theological stream which then became the determining one for the development of the Roman Catholic Church of the West, debated in the following way about what the Greek had argued. He said: Ransom can only be paid to a being who really exists. But death has no reality, death is only the outer limit of reality, death itself is not real and, therefore, the ransom money could not have been paid to Death.
Now criticism of Alcuin's way of thinking is not what matters here. For to someone who, to a certain extent, can see through the interrelations of the facts, the view that death is not something real resembles the view which says: Cold is not something real, it is just a decrease in warmth, it is only a lesser warmth. Because the cold isn't real I won't wear a winter coat in winter because I'm not going to protect myself against something that isn't real. But we will leave that aside. We want rather to take the argument between Alcuin and the Greek purely positively and will ask what was really happening there. For it is indeed quite noticeable that it is not the concept of redemption itself that is discussed. It is not discussed in such a way that in a certain sense both personalities, the Greek and the Roman Catholic theologian, accept the same point of view, but in such a way that the Roman Catholic theologian shifts the standpoint entirely before he takes it up at all. He does not go on speaking in the way he had just done, but moves the whole problem into a completely different direction. He asks: Is death something real or not?—and objects that, indeed, death is not real.
This directs us at the outset to the fact that two views are clashing here which arise out of completely different constitutions of soul. And, indeed, this is the case. The Greek continued, as it were, the direction which, in the Greek culture, had basically faded away between Plato and Aristotle. In Plato there was still something alive of the ancient wisdom of humanity; that wisdom which takes us across to the ancient Orient where, indeed, in ancient times a primal wisdom had lived but which had then fallen more and more into decadence. In Plato, if we are able to understand him properly, we find the last offshoots, if I can so call them, of this primal oriental wisdom. And then, like a rapidly developing metamorphosis, Aristotelianism sets in which, fundamentally, presents a completely different constitution of soul from the Platonic one. Aristotelianism represents a completely different element in the development of humanity from Platonism. And, if we follow Aristotelianism further, it, too, takes on different forms, different metamorphoses, but all of which have a recognizable similarity. Thus we see how Platonism lives on like an ancient heritage in this Greek who has to contend against Alcuin, and how in Alcuin, on the other hand, Aristotelianism is already present. And we are directed, by looking at these two individuals, to that fluctuation which took place on European soil between two—one cannot really say world-views—but two human constitutions of soul, one of which has its origin in ancient times in the Orient, and another, which we do not find in the Orient but which, entering in later, arose in the central regions of civilization and was first grasped by Aristotle. In Aristotle, however, this only sounds a first quiet note, for much of Greek culture was still alive in him. It develops then with particular vehemence in the Roman culture within which it had been prepared long before Aristotle, and, indeed, before Plato. So that we see how, since the eighth century BC on the Italian peninsula a particular culture, or the first hints of it, was being prepared alongside that which lived on the Greek peninsula as a sort of last offshoot of the oriental constitution of soul. And when we go into the differences between these two modes of human thought we find important historical impulses. For what is expressed in these ways of thinking went over later into the feeling life of human beings; into the configuration of human actions and so on.
Now we can ask ourselves: So what was living in that which developed in ancient times as a world-view in the Orient, and which then, like a latecomer, found its [last] offshoots in Platonism—and, indeed, still in Neoplatonism? It was a highly spiritual culture which arose from an inner perception living pre-eminently in pictures, in imaginations; but pictures not permeated by full consciousness, not yet permeated by the full I-consciousness of human beings. In the spiritual life of the ancient Orient, of which the Veda and Vedanta are the last echoes, stupendous pictures opened up of what lives in the human being as the spiritual. But it existed in a—I beg you not to misunderstand the word and not to confuse it with usual dreaming—it existed in a dreamlike, dim way, so that this soul-life was not permeated (durchwellt) and irradiated (durchstrahlt) by what lives in the human being when he becomes clearly conscious of his 'I' and his own being. The oriental was well aware that his being existed before birth, that it returns through death to the spiritual world in which it existed before birth or conception. The oriental gazed on that which passed through births and deaths. But he did not see as such that inner feeling which lives in the `I am'. It was as if it were dull and hazy, as though poured out in a broad perception of the soul (Gesamtseelenanschauung) which did not concentrate to such a point as that of the I-experience. Into what, then, did the oriental actually gaze when he possessed his instinctive perception?
One can still feel how this oriental soul-constitution was completely different from that of later humanity when, for an understanding of this and perhaps prepared through spiritual science, one sinks meditatively into those remarkable writings which are ascribed to Dionysius the Areopagite.7 Rudolf Steiner drew attention at different times to the fact that the content of the writings of 533 A.D., attributed to Dionysius the Areopagite, do indeed stem from the person of this name mentioned in The Acts of the Apostles 17, 34. See the lectures on 17 and 25 March 1907 in Christianity Began as a Religion and Festivals of the Seasons respectively. I will not go into the question of the authorship now, I have already spoken about it on a number of occasions. 'Nothingness' (das Nichts) is still spoken of there as a reality, and the existence of the external world, in the way one views it in ordinary consciousness, is simply contrasted against this [nothingness] as a different reality. This talk of nothingness then continues. In Scotus Erigena,8 Johannes Scotus Erigena (c. 810–877) translator of the writings of Dionysius the Areopagite into Latin (see note 7). who lived at the court of Charles the Bald, one still finds echoes of it, and we find the last echo then in the fifteenth century in Nicolas of Cusa9 Nicolaus of Cusa (or Kures) (1401–1464), cardinal. But what was meant by the nothingness one finds in Dionysius the Areopagite and of that which the oriental spoke of as something self-evident to him? This fades then completely. What was this nothingness for the oriental? It was something real for him. He turned his gaze to the world of the senses around him, and said: This sense-world is spread out in space, flows in time, and in ordinary life world, is spread out in space, one says that what is extended in space and flows in time is something.
But what the oriental saw—that which was a reality for him, which passes through births and deaths—was not contained in the space in which the minerals are to be found, in which the plants unfold, the animals move and the human being as a physical being moves and acts. And it was also not contained in that time in which our thoughts, feelings and will-impulses occur. The oriental was fully aware that one must go beyond this space in which physical things are extended and move, and beyond this time in which our soul-forces of ordinary life are active. One must enter a completely different world; that world which, for the external existence of time and space, is a nothing but which, nevertheless, is something real. The oriental sensed something in contrast to the phenomena of the world which the European still senses at most in the realm of real numbers.
When a European has fifty francs he has something. If he spends twenty-five francs of this he still has twenty-five francs; if he then spends fifteen francs he still has ten; if he spends this he has nothing. If now he continues to spend he has five, ten, fifteen, twenty-five francs in debts. He still has nothing; but, indeed, he has something very real when, instead of simply an empty wallet, he has twenty-five or fifty francs in debts. In the real world it also signifies something very real if one has debts. There is a great difference in one's whole situation in life between having nothing and having fifty francs' worth of debts. These debts of fifty francs are forces just as influential on one's situation in life as, on the other side and in an opposite sense, are fifty francs of credit. In this area the European will probably admit to the reality of debts for, in the real world, there always has to be something there when one has debts. The debts that one has oneself may still seem a very negative amount, but for the person to whom they are owed they are a very positive amount!
So, when it is not just a matter of the individual but of the world, the opposite side of zero from the credit side is truly something very real. The oriental felt—not because he somehow speculated about it but because his perception necessitated it he felt: Here, on the one side, I experience that which cannot be observed in space or in time; something which, for the things and events of space and time, is nothing but which, nevertheless, is a reality—but a different reality.
It was only through misunderstanding that there then arose what occidental civilization gave itself up to under the leadership of Rome—the creation of the world out of nothing with `nothing' seen as absolute `zero'. In the Orient, where these things were originally conceived, the world does not arise out of nothing but out of the reality I have just indicated. And an echo of what vibrates through all the oriental way of thinking right down to Plato—the impulse of eternity of an ancient world-view—lived in the Greek who, at the court of Charlemagne, had to debate with Alcuin. And in this theologian Alcuin there lived a rejection of the spiritual life for which, in the Orient, this `nothing' was the outer form. And thus, when the Greek spoke of death, whose causes lie in the spiritual world, as something real, Alcuin could only answer: But death is nothing and therefore cannot receive ransom.
You see, the whole polarity between the ancient oriental way of thinking, reaching to Plato, and what followed later is expressed in this [one] significant moment when Alcuin debated at the court of Charlemagne with the Greek. For, what was it that had meanwhile entered in to European civilization since Plato, particularly through the spread of Romanism? There had entered that way of thinking which one has to comprehend through the fact that it is directed primarily to what the human being experiences between birth and death. And the constitution of soul which occupies itself primarily with the human being's experiences between birth and death is the logical, legal one—the logical-dialectical-legal one. The Orient had nothing of a logical, dialectical nature and, least of all, a legal one. The Occident brought logical, legal thinking so strongly into the oriental way of thinking that we ourselves find religious feeling permeated with a legalistic element. In the Sistine Chapel in Rome, painted by the master-hand of Michelangelo, we see looming towards us, Christ as judge giving judgment on the good and the evil.
A legal, dialectical element has entered into the thoughts concerning the course of the world. This was completely alien to the oriental way of thinking. There was nothing there like guilt and atonement or redemptinn. For [in this oriental way of thinking] was precisely that view of the metamorphosis through which the eternal element [in the human being] transforms itself through births and deaths. There was that which lives in the concept of karma. Later, however, everything was fixed into a way of looking at things which is actually only valid for, and can only encompass, life between birth and death. But this life between birth and death was just what had evaded the oriental. He looked far more to the core of man's being. He had little understanding for what took place between birth and death. And now, within this occidental culture, the way of thinking which comprehends primarily what takes place within the span between birth and death increased [and did so] through those forces possessed by the human being by virtue of having clothed his soul-and-spirit nature with a physical and etheric body. In this constitution, in the inner experience of the soul-and-spirit element and in the nature of this experience, which arises through the fact that one is submerged with one's soul-and-spirit nature in a physical body, comes the inner comprehension of the 'I'. This is why it happens in the Occident that the human being feels an inner urge to lay hold of his 'I' as something divine. We see this urge, to comprehend the 'I' as something divine, arise in the medieval mystics; in Eckhart, in Tauler and in others. The comprehension of the 'I' crystallizes out with full force in the Middle (or Central) culture. Thus we can distinguish between the Eastern culture—the time in which the 'I' is first experienced, but dimly—and the Middle (or Central) culture—primarily that in which the 'I' is experienced. And we see how this 'I' is experienced in the most manifold metamorphoses. First of all in that dim, dawning way in which it arises in Eckhart, Tauler and other mystics, and then more and more distinctly during the development of all that can originate out of this I-culture.
We then see how, within the I-culture of the Centre, another aspect arises. At the end of the eighteenth century something comes to the fore in Kant10Immanuel Kant (1724–1804): Critique of Pure Reason, 1781; Prolegemena, 1783. which, fundamentally, cannot be explained out of the onward flow of this I-culture. For what is it that arises through Kant? Kant looks at our perception, our apprehension (Erkennen), of nature and cannot come to terms with it. Knowledge of nature, for him, breaks down into subjective views ( Subjektivitäten); he does not penetrate as far as the 'I' despite the fact that he continually speaks of it and even, in some categories, in his perceptions of time and space, would like to encompass all nature through the 'I'. Yet he does not push through to a true experience of the 'I'. He also constructs a practical philosophy with the categorical imperative which is supposed to manifest itself out of unfathomable regions of the human soul. Here again the 'I' does not appear.
In Kant's philosophy it is strange. The full weight of dialectics, of logical-dialectical-legal thinking is there, in which everything is tending towards the 'I', but he cannot reach the point of really understanding the 'I' philosophically. There must be something preventing him here. Then comes Fichte, a pupil of Kant's, who with full force wishes his whole philosophy to well up out of the 'I' and who, through its simplicity, presents as the highest tenet of his philosophy the sentence: `I am'. And everything that is truly scientific must follow from this `I am'. One should be able, as it were, to deduce, to read from this 'I am' an entire picture of the world. Kant cannot reach the 'I am'. Fichte immediately afterwards, while still a pupil of Kant's, hurls the `I am' at him. And everyone is amazed—this is a pupil of Kant's speaking like this! And Fichte says:11Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) Erste und zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre und Verstwh einer neuen Darstellung der Wiyenschaftslehre (First and Second Introduction into the Doctrine of Knowledge and an Attempt at a New Presentation of the doctrine of Knowledge). As far as he can understand it, Kant, if he could really think to the end, would have to think the same as me. It is so inexplicable to Fichte that Kant thinks differently from him, that he says: If Kant would only take things to their full conclusion, he would have to think [as I do]; he too, would have to come to the 'I am'. And Fichte expresses this even more clearly by saying: I would rather take the whole of Kant's critique for a random game of ideas haphazardly thrown together than to consider it the work of a human mind, if my philosophy did not logically follow from Kant's. Kant, of course, rejects this. He wants nothing to do with the conclusions drawn by Fichte.
We now see how there follows on from Fichte what then flowered as German idealistic philosophy in Schelling and Hegel, and which provoked all the battles of which I spoke, in part, in my lectures on the limits to a knowledge of nature.12Grenzen der Naturerkenntnis (Limits to a Knowledge of Nature (GA 322)—eight lectures given during the first course (Hochschulkurs) of the School of Spiritual Science in Dornach, 27 September to 3 October 1920 (GA 322). But we find something curious. We see how Hegel lives in a crystal-clear [mental] framework of the logical-dialectical-legal element and draws from it a world-view—but a world-view that is interested only in what occurs between birth and death. You can go through the whole of Hegel's philosophy and you will find nothing that goes beyond birth and death. It confines everything in world history, religion, art and science solely to experiences occurring between birth and death.
What then is the strange thing that happened here? Now, what came out in Fichte, Schelling and Hegel—this strongest development of the Central culture in which the 'I' came to full consciousness, to an inner experience—was still only a reaction, a last reaction to something else. For one can understand Kant only when one bears the following properly in mind. (I am coming now to yet another significant point to which a great deal can be traced). You see, Kant was still—this is clearly evident from his earlier writings—a pupil of the rationalism of the eighteenth century, which lived with genius in Leibnitz and pedantically in Wolff. One can see that for this rationalism the important thing was not to come truly to a spiritual reality. Kant therefore rejected it—this `thing in itself' as he called it—but the important thing for him was to prove. Sure proof! Kant's writings are remarkable also in this respect. He wrote his Critique of Pure Reason in which he is actually asking: `How must the world be so that things can be proved in it?' Not 'What are the realities in it?' But he actually asks: 'How must I imagine the world so that logically, dialectically, I can give proofs in it?' This is the only point he is concerned with and thus he tries in his Prologomena to give every future metaphysics which has a claim to being truly scientific, a metaphysics for what in his way of thinking can be proven: `Away with everything else! The devil take the reality of the world—just let me have the art of proving! What's it to me what reality is; if I can't prove it I shan't trouble myself over it!'
Those individuals did not, of course, think in this way who wrote books like, for example, Christian Wolff's13Baron Christian von Wolff, philosopher and mathematician, Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt, 1719. Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt (Reasoned Thoughts an God, the World, and the Soul of Man, and All Things Generally). What mattered for them was to have a clean, self-contained system of proof, in the way that they see proof. Kant lived in this sphere, but there was still something there which, although an excrescence squeezed out of the world-view of the Centre, nevertheless fitted into it. But Kant had something else which makes it inexplicable how he could become Fichte's teacher. And yet he gives Fichte a stimulus, and Fichte comes back at him with the strong emphasis of the 'I am'; comes back, indeed, not with proofs—one would not look for these in Fichte—but with a fully developed inner life of soul. In Fichte there emerges, with all the force of the inner life of soul, that which, in the Wolffians and Leibnitzites, can seem insipid. Fichte constructs his philosophy, in a wealth of pure concepts, out of the 'I am'; but in him they are filled with life. So, too, are they in Schelling and in Hegel. So what then had happened with Kant who was the bridge? Now, one comes to the significant point when one traces how Kant developed. Something else became of this pupil of Wolff by virtue of the fact that the English philosopher, David Hume,14David Hume (1711–1776), philosopher. awoke him, as Kant himself says, out of his dull dogmatic slumber. What is it that entered Kant here, which Fichte could no longer understand? There entered into Kant here—it fitted badly in his case because he was too involved with the culture of Central Europe—that which is now the culture of the West. This came to meet him in the person of David Hume and it was here that the culture of the West entered Kant. And in what does the peculiarity [of this culture] lie? In the oriental culture we find that the 'I' still lives below, dimly, in a dream-like state in the soul-experiences which express themselves, spread out, in imaginative pictures. In the Western culture we find that, in a certain sense, the 'I' is smothered (erdrückt) by the purely external phenomena (Tatsachen). The 'I' is indeed present, and is present not dimly, but bores itself into the phenomena. And here, for example, people develop a strange psychology. They do not talk here about the soul-life in the way Fichte did, who wanted to work out everything from the one point of the 'I', but they talk about thoughts which come together by association. People talk about feelings, mental pictures and sensations, and say these associate—and also will-impulses associate. One talks about the inner soul-life in terms of thoughts which associate.
Fichte speaks of the 'I'; this radiates out thoughts. In the West the 'I' is completely omitted because it is absorbed—soaked up by the thoughts and feelings which one treats as though they were independent of it, associating and separating again. And one follows the life of the soul as though mental pictures linked up and separated. Read Spencer,15Herbert Spencer (1820–1903), philosopher. read John Stuart Mill16John Stuart Mill (1806–1873), philosopher. read the American philosophers. When they come to talk of psychology there is this curious view that does not exclude the 'I' as in the Orient, because it is developed dimly there, but which makes full demand of the 'I'; letting it, however, sink down into the thinking, feeling and willing life of the soul. One could say: In the oriental the 'I' is still above thinking, feeling and willing; it has not yet descended to the level of thinking, feeling and willing. In the human being of the Western culture the 'I' is already below this sphere. It is below the surface of thinking, feeling and willing so that it is no longer noticed, and thinking, feeling and willing are then spoken of as independent forces.

This is what came to Kant in the form of the philosophy of David Hume. Then the Central region of the earth's culture still set itself against this with all force in Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. After them the culture of the West overwhelms everything that is there, with Darwinism and Spencerism.
One will only be able to come to an understanding of what is living in humanity's development if one investigates these deeper forces. One then finds that something developed in a natural way in the Orient which actually was purely a spiritual life. In the Central areas something developed which was dialectical-legal, which actually brought forth the idea of the State, because it is to this that it can be applied. It is such thinkers as Fichte, Schelling and Hegel who, with enormous sympathy, construct a unified image (Gebilde) of the State. But then a culture emerges in the West which proceeds from a constitution of soul in which the 'I' is absorbed, takes its course below the level of thinking, feeling and willing; and where, in the mental and feeling life, people speak of associations. If only one would apply this thinking to the economic life! That is its proper place. People went completely amiss when they started applying [this thinking] to something other than the economic life. There it is great, is of genius. And had Spencer, John Stuart Mill and David Hume applied to the institutions of the economic life what they wasted on philosophy it would have been magnificent. If the human beings living in Central Europe had limited to the State what is given them as their natural endowment, and if they had not, at the same time, also wanted thereby to include the spiritual life and the economic life, something magnificent could have come out of it. For, with what Hegel was able to think, with what Fichte was able to think, one would have been able—had one remained within the legal-political configuration which, in the threefold organism, we wish to separate out as the structure of the State17Towards Social Renewal, 1919, (GA 23).—to attain something truly great. But, because there hovered before these minds the idea that they had to create a structure for the State which included the economic life and the spiritual life, there arose only caricatures in the place of a true form for the State. And the spiritual life was anyway only a heritage of the ancient Orient. It was just that people did not know that they were still living from this heritage of the ancient East. The useful statements, for example, of Christian theology—indeed, the useful statements still within our materialistic sciences—are either the heritage of the ancient East, or a changeling of dialectical-legal thinking, or are already adopted, as was done by Spencer and Mill, from the Western culture which is particularly suited for the economic life.
Thus the spiritual thinking of the ancient Orient had been distributed over the earth, but in an instinctive way that is no longer of any use today. Because today it is decadent, it is dialectical-political thinking which was rendered obsolete by the world catastrophe [World War I]. For there was no one less suited to thinking economically than the pupils of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel. When they began to create a State which, above all, was to become great through its economy, they had of necessity (selbstverständlich) to fail, for this was not what, by nature, was, endowed to them. In accordance with the historical development of humanity, spiritual thinking, political thinking and economic thinking were apportioned to the East, the Centre, and the West respectively. But we have arrived at a point of humanity's development when understanding, a common understanding, must spread equally over all humanity. How can this come about?
This can only happen out of the initiation-culture, out of the new spiritual science, which does not develop one-sidedly, but considers everything that appears in all areas as a three-foldness that has evolved of its own accord. This science must really consider the threefold aspect also in social life; in this case (as a three-foldness) encompassing the whole earth. Spiritual science, however, cannot be extended through natural abilities; it can only be spread by people accepting those who see into these things, who can really experience the spiritual sphere, the political sphere and the economic sphere as three separate areas. The unity of human beings all over the earth is due to the fact that they combine in themselves what was divided between three spheres. They themselves organize it in the social organism in such a way that it can exist in harmony before their eyes. This, however, can only follow from spiritual-scientific training. And we stand here at a point where we must say: In ancient times we see individual personalities, we see them expressing in their words what was the spirit of the time. But when we examine it closely—in the oriental culture, for example—we find that, fundamentally, there lives instinctively in the masses a constitution of soul which in a remarkable; quite natural way was in accord with what these individuals spoke.
This correspondence, however, became less and less. In our times we see the development of the opposite extreme. We see instincts arising in the masses which are the opposite of what is beneficial for humanity. We see things arising that absolutely call for the qualities that may arise in individuals who are able to penetrate the depths of spiritual science. No good will come from instincts, but only from the understanding (that Dr. Unger also spoke of here)18In the third week of the first course (of the School of Spiritual Science), Dr Carl Unger (1822–1929) gave lectures under the title of 'Rudolf Steiner's Works'. These six lectures, edited by Unger, can be found in Volume I of Carl Unger's Writings, Stuttgart, 1964. which, as is often stressed, every human being can bring towards the spiritual investigator if he really opens himself to healthy human reason. Thus there will come a culture in which the single individual, with his ever-deeper penetration into the depths of the spiritual world, will be of particular importance, and in which die one who penetrates in this way will be valued, just as someone who works in some craft is valued. One does not go to the tailor to have boots made or to the shoemaker to be shaved, so why should people go to someone else for what one needs as a world-view other than to the person who is initiated into it? And it is, indeed, just this that, particularly today and in the most intense sense, is necessary for the good of human beings even though there is a reaction against it, which shows how humanity still resists what is beneficial for it. This is the terrible battle—the grave situation—in which we find ourselves.
At no other time has there been a greater need to listen carefully to what individuals know concerning one thing or another. Nor has there been a greater need for people with knowledge of specific subject areas to be active in social life—not from a belief in authority but out of common sense and out of agreement based on common sense. But, to begin with, the instincts oppose this and people believe that some sort of good can be achieved from levelling everything. This is the serious battle in which we stand. Sympathy and antipathy are of no help here, nor is living in slogans. Only a clear observation of the facts can help. For today great questions are being decided—the questions as to whether the individual or the masses have significance. In other times this was not important because the masses and the individual were in accord with one another; individuals were, in a certain sense, simply speaking for the masses. We are approaching more and more that time when the individual must find completely within himself the source of what he has to find and which he has then to put into the social life; and [what we are now seeing] is only the last resistance against this validity of the individual and an ever larger and larger number of individuals. One can see plainly how that which spiritual science shows is also proved everywhere in these significant points. We talk of associations which are necessary in the economic life, and use a particular thinking for this. This has developed in the culture of the West from letting thoughts associate. If one could take what John Stuart Mill does with logic, if one could remove those thoughts from that sphere and apply them to the economic life, they would fit there. The associations which would then come in there would be exactly those which do not fit into psychology. Even in what appears in the area of human development, spiritual science follows reality.
Thus spiritual science, if fully aware of the seriousness of the present world situation, knows what a great battle is taking place between the threefold social impulse that can come from spiritual science and that which throws itself against this threefoldness as the wave of Bolshevism, which would lead to great harm (Unheil) amongst humanity. And there is no third element other than these two. The battle has to take place between these two. People must see this! Everything else is already decadent. Whoever looks with an open mind at the conditions in which we are placed, must conclude that it is essential today to gather all our forces together so that this whole terrible Ahrimanic affair can be repulsed.
This building stands here,19The first Goetheanum building, begun in 1913, was already put into use in 1920, although still under construction supervised by Rudolf Steiner and with the interior not yet finished. On New Year's Eve 1922–3 it was destroyed by fire. incomplete though it is for the time being. Today we cannot get from the Central countries that which for the most part, and in addition to what has come to us from the neutral states, has brought this building to this stage. We must have contributions from the countries of the former Entente. Understanding must be developed here for what is to become a unified culture containing spirit, politics and economics. For people must get away from a one:sided tendency and must follow those who also understand something of politics and economics, who do not work only in dialectics, but, also being engaged with economic impulses, have insight into the spiritual, and do not want to create states in which the State itself can run the economy. The Western peoples will have to realize that something else must evolve in addition to the special gift they will have in the future with regard to forming economic associations. The skill in forming associations has so far been applied at the wrong end, i.e. in the field of Psychology. What must evolve is understanding of the political-state element, which has other sources than the economic life, and also of the spiritual element. But at present the Central countries lie powerless, so people in the Western regions—one could not expect this of the Orient—will have to see what the Purpose of this building is! It is necessary for us to consider What must be done so that real provision is made for a new culture that should be presented everywhere in the university education of the future—here we have to show the way. In the foundation of the Waldorf Schools the culture has proved to be capable of bringing light into primary education. But for this we need the understanding support of the widest circles.
Above all we need the means. For everything which, in a higher or lower sense, is called a school, we need the frame of mind I have already tried to awaken at the opening of the Waldorf School in Stuttgart.20The Free Waldorf School was founded in Stuttgart in the spring of 1919 by Dr Emil Molt for the children, to begin with, of the employees of the Waldorf-Astoria cigarette factory. The school was under the supervision of Rudolf Steiner who appointed the teachers and gave the preparatory seminar courses. I said in my opening speech there: `This is one Waldorf school. It is well and good that we have it, but for itself it is nothing; it is only something if, in the next quarter of a year, we build ten such Waldorf schools and then others'. The world did not understand this, it had no money for such a thing. For it rests on the standpoint: Oh, the ideals are too lofty, too pure for us to bring dirty money to them; better to keep it in our pockets; that's the proper place for dirty money. The ideals, oh, they're too pure, one can't contaminate them with money! Of course, with purity of this kind the embodiment of ideals cannot be attained, if dirty money is not brought to them. And thus we have to consider that, up to now, we have stopped at one Waldorf school which cannot progress properly because in the autumn we found ourselves in great money difficulties. These have been obviated for the time being, but at Easter we shall be faced with them again. And then, after a comparatively short time, we will ask: Should we give up? And we shall have to give up if, before then, an understanding is not forthcoming which dips vigorously into its pockets.
It is thus a matter of awakening understanding in this respect. I don't believe that much understanding would arise if we were to say that we wanted something for the building in Dornach, or some such thing—as has been shown already. But—and one still finds understanding for this today—if one wants to create sanatoria or the like, one gets money, and as much as one wants! This is not exactly what we want—we don't want to build a host of sanatoria—we agree fully with creating them as far as they are necessary; but here it is a matter, above all, of nurturing that spiritual culture whose necessity will indeed prove itself through what this course21The first anthroposophical course of the Free School for Spiritual Science took place at the Goetheanum from 26 September to 16 October 1920. See also notes 1,3,12, and 18. I has attempted to accomplish. This is what I tried to suggest, to give a stimulus to what I expressed here a few days ago, in the words 'World Fellowship of Schools' (Weltschulverein).22i.e., a form of international support body for Waldorf Schools. Rudolf Steiner suggested the founding of a World Fellowship of Schools during an assembly of teachers on 16 October 1920. There is no available transcript of this talk.
Our German friends have departed but it is not a question of depending on them for this 'World Fellowship'. It depends on those who, as friends, have come here, for the most part from all possible regions of the non-German world—and who are still sitting here now—that they understand these words 'World Fellowship of Schools' because it is vital that we found school upon school in all areas of the world out of the pedagogical spirit which rules in the Waldorf School. We have to be able to extend this school until we are able to move into higher education of the kind we are hoping for here. For this, however, we have to be in a position to complete this building and everything that belongs to it, and be constantly able to support that which is necessary in order to work here; to be productive, to work on the further extension of all the separate sciences in the spirit of spiritual science.
People ask one how much money one needs for all this. One cannot say how much, because there never is an uppermost limit. And, of course, we will not be able to found a World Fellowship of Schools simply by creating a committee of twelve or fifteen or thirty people who work out nice statutes as to how a World Fellowship of Schools of this kind should work. That is all pointless. I attach no value to programmes or to statutes but only to the work of active people who work with understanding. It will be possible to establish this World Fellowship—well, we shall not be able to go to London for some time—in the Hague or some such place, if a basis can be created, and by other means if the friends who are about to go to Norway or Sweden or Holland, or any other country—England, France, America and so on—awaken in every human being whom they can reach the well-founded conviction that there has to be a World Fellowship of Schools. It ought to go through the world like wildfire that a World Fellowship must arise to provide the material means for the spiritual culture that is intended here.
If one is able in other matters, as a single individual, to convince possibly hundreds and hundreds of people, why should one not be able in a short time—for the decline is happening so quickly that we only have a short time—to have an effect on many people as a single individual, so that if one came to the Hague a few weeks later one would see how widespread was the thought that: 'The creation of a World Fellowship of Schools is necessary, it is just that there are no means for it.' What we are trying to do from Dornach is an historical necessity. One will only be able to talk of the inauguration of this World Fellowship of Schools when the idea of it already exists. It is simply utopian to set up committees and found a World Fellowship—this is pointless! But to work from person to person, and to spread quickly the realization, the well-founded realization, that it is so necessary—this is what must precede the founding. Spiritual science lives in realities. This is why it does not get involved with proposals of schemes for a founding but points to what has to happen in reality—and human beings are indeed realities—so that such a thing has some prospects.
So what is important here is that we finally learn from spiritual science how to stand in real life. I would never get involved with a simply utopian founding of the World Fellowship of Schools, but would always be of the opinion that this World Fellowship can only come about when a sufficiently large number of people are convinced of its necessity. It must be created so that what is necessary for humanity—it has already proved to be so from our course here—can happen. This World Fellowship of Schools must be created.
Please see what is meant by this Fellowship in all international life, in the right sense! I would like, in this request, to round off today what, in a very different way in our course, has spoken to humanity through those who were here and of whom we have the hope and the wish that they carry it out into the world. The World Fellowship of Schools can be the answer of the world to what was put before it like a question; a question taken from the real forces of human evolution, that is, human history. So let what can happen for the World Fellowship of Schools, in accordance with the conviction you have been able to gain here, happen! In this there rings out what I wanted to say today.
Erster Vortrag
Es ist in den Vorträgen, die hier während des Kursus über Geschichte gehalten worden sind, mehreres erwähnt worden, das zu betrachten gerade in der gegenwärtigen Zeit von einer ganz besonderen Wichtigkeit sein kann. Zunächst ist in bezug auf den geschichtlichen Verlauf der Menschheitsentwickelung die ja oftmals besprochene Frage erwähnt worden, ob die hauptsächlichsten treibenden Kräfte in dieser Entwickelung die einzelnen hervorragenden, tonangebenden Persönlichkeiten seien, oder ob das Wesentliche bewirkt werde nicht von diesen einzelnen Persönlichkeiten, sondern von den Massen. Es ist dieses in vielen Kreisen immer ein strittiger Punkt gewesen, und über ihn wurde wirklich mehr aus Sympathie und Antipathie heraus entschieden als aus wirklicher Erkenntnis. Das ist die eine Tatsache, die ich gewissermaßen als wichtig erwähnen möchte. Die andere Tatsache, die ich gerade aus den geschichtlichen Betrachtungen heraus als wichtig hier notieren möchte, ist die folgende: Mit einem deutlichen Kundgeben ist im Beginn des 19. Jahrhunderts Wilhelm von Humboldt aufgetreten, indem er verlangt hat, die Geschichte solle so betrachtet werden, daß man nicht nur die einzelnen Tatsachen in Erwägung zieht, die äußerlich in der physischen Welt zu beobachten sind, sondern aus einer zusammenfassenden, synthetisierenden Kraft heraus dasjenige sieht, was im geschichtlichen Werden wirksam ist, was aber eigentlich nur gefunden werden kann von demjenigen, der in einem gewissen Sinne dichterisch, aber dann eigentlich die Wahrheit dichtend, die geschichtlichen Tatsachen zusammenzufassen weiß. Es ist auch darauf aufmerksam gemacht worden, wie im Laufe des 19. Jahrhunderts dann gerade die entgegengesetzte geschichtliche Denkweise und Gesinnung eine besondere Ausbildung erfahren hat, wie keineswegs Ideen in der Geschichte verfolgt worden sind, sondern eben nur der Sinn für die äußere Tatsachenwelt entwickelt worden ist. Und es ist darauf aufmerksam gemacht worden, daß gerade über die letztere Frage eigentlich erst zur Klarheit gekommen werden kann aus der Geisteswissenschaft heraus, weil ja erst die Geisteswissenschaft die wirklichen treibenden Kräfte des geschichtlichen Werdens der Menschheit enthüllen kann. Humboldt war eine solche Geisteswissenschaft noch nicht zugänglich. Er sprach von Ideen, aber Ideen haben doch keine treibende Kraft. Ideen als solche sind eben Abstraktionen, wie ich schon gestern hier erwähnte. Und derjenige, der auch Ideen als die treibenden Kräfte der Geschichte finden möchte, könnte niemals beweisen, daß diese Ideen wirklich etwas tun, denn sie sind nichts Wesenhaftes, und nur Wesenhaftes kann etwas tun. Die Geisteswissenschaft deutet auf wirkliche geistige Kräfte hin, die hinter den sinnlich-physischen Tatsachen sind, und in solchen wirklichen geistigen Kräften liegen die Motoren des Geschichtlichen, wenn auch diese geistigen Kräfte für den Menschen dann eben durch Ideen ausgedrückt werden müssen.
Aber über all diese Dinge kommen wir nur zur Klarheit, wenn wir einen tieferen Blick eben gerade vom geisteswissenschaftlichen Standpunkte aus in das geschichtliche Werden der Menschheit werfen, und wir wollen es heute einmal so tun, daß durch unsere Betrachtungen einige Tatsachen uns erfließen, die gerade für die Beurteilung der gegenwärtigen Menschheitssituation wichtig sein können. Ich habe schon öfter erwähnt, daß die Geisteswissenschaft, wenn sie geschichtliche Betrachtungen anstellt, dann eigentlich eine Symptomatologie betreiben müsse, eine Symptomatologie, die darin besteht, daß man sich bewußt ist: Hinter dem, was als physisch-sinnlicher Tatsachenstrom abläuft, liegen die treibenden geistigen Kräfte. Aber es gibt überall in dem geschichtlichen Werden Punkte, wo das eigentlich Wesenhafte symptomatisch an die Oberfläche tritt und wo man es beurteilen kann aus den Erscheinungen heraus, wenn man nur die Möglichkeit hat, in seiner Erkenntnis von diesen Erscheinungen aus mehr hineinzudringen in die Tiefen des geschichtlichen Werdens.

Ich möchte das durch eine einfache versinnlichende Zeichnung klarmachen. Nehmen wir einmal an, dies wäre ein Strom von geschichtlichen Tatsachen (siehe Zeichnung). Dasjenige, was treibende Kräfte sind, liegt eigentlich für die gewöhnliche Beobachtung unter dem Strom dieser Tatsachen. Wenn etwa ein Seelenauge diesen Strom der Tatsachen so beobachtet, dann würde unter dem Strom der Tatsachen das eigentliche Wirken der treibenden Kräfte liegen (rot). Aber es gibt bedeutsame Punkte innerhalb des Tatsachenstromes. Und diese bedeutsamen Punkte zeichnen sich eben dadurch aus, daß bei ihnen das sonst sich Verbergende an die Oberfläche tritt. So daß wir sagen können: Hier würde an einer besonderen Erscheinung, die man nur richtig abschätzen muß, klarwerden können, was auch sonst überall wirkt, was sich aber nicht an so prägnanten Erscheinungen zeigt. Nehmen wir an, das (siehe Zeichnung) wäre in irgendeinem Jahre der Weltgeschichte, was sich hier abspielt etwa 800 nach Christi Geburt. Dasjenige, was für Europa, sagen wir, für Westeuropa bedeutsam war, wirkte natürlich auch vorher, wirkte auch nachher; aber nicht in einer so prägnanten Art zeigte es sich in der vorhergehenden Zeit und in der nachfolgenden Zeit, wie gerade da. Wenn man auf eine solche Geschichtsbetrachtung weist, die hinschaut auf prägnante Punkte, so liegt eine solche durchaus im Sinne des Goetheanismus. Denn Goethe wollte überhaupt alle Weltbetrachtung so einrichten, daß auf gewisse prägnante Punkte hingeschaut werde und aus dem, was in solchen prägnanten Punkten erschaut werden kann, dann der übrige Gehalt des Weltgeschehens erkannt werden sollte. Goethe sagt geradezu, innerhalb der Fülle der Tatsachen komme es darauf an, überall einen prägnanten Punkt zu finden, von dem aus sich die Nachbargebiete überschauen lassen, von dem aus sich viel enträtseln läßt.
Nun, nehmen wir dieses Jahr 800 etwa. Da können wir auf eine Tatsache hinweisen in der westeuropäischen Menschheitsentwickelung, die gegenüber der gewöhnlichen Geschichtsbetrachtung unbedeutend erscheinen könnte, die man vielleicht gar nicht beachtenswert findet für das, was man sonst Geschichte nennt, die aber doch für eine tiefere Betrachtung des Menschheitswerdens eben ein prägnanter Punkt ist. Um dieses Jahr herum etwa war eine Art theologisch-gelehrter Streit zwischen dem Manne, der eine Art Hofphilosoph des Frankenreiches war, Alkuin, und einem damals im Frankenreiche lebenden Griechen. Der Grieche, der bewandert war gerade in der besonderen Seelenverfassung des Griechenvolkes, die sich auf ihn herüber vererbt hatte, hatte die Prinzipien des Christentums beurteilen wollen und kam auf den Begriff der Erlösung. Er stellte die Frage: Wem ist denn eigentlich bei dieser Erlösung durch den Christus Jesus das Lösegeld ausbezahlt worden? — Er, der griechische Denker, kam zu der Lösung, dem Tod sei das Lösegeld ausbezahlt worden. Also es war gewissermaßen eine Art Erlösungstheorie, die dieser Grieche aus dieser ganz griechischen Denkweise, die eben das Christentum kennenlernt, entwickelt hat. Dem Tod sei das Lösegeld durch die Weltenmächte ausbezahlt worden.
Alkuin, der damals in jener theologischen Strömung drinnenstand, welche dann maßgebend geworden ist für die Entwickelung der römisch-katholischen Kirche des Abendlandes, diskutierte in der folgenden Weise über das, was dieser Grieche vorgebracht hatte. Er sagte: Das Lösegeld kann doch nur einem Wesen ausbezahlt werden, das wirklich ist; aber der Tod hat doch keine Wirklichkeit, der Tod schließt nur die Wirklichkeit ab, der Tod ist nichts Wirkliches; also könne auch nicht das Lösegeld an den Tod bezahlt worden sein.
Nun, es kommt jetzt nicht darauf an, die Alkuinsche Denkweise zu kritisieren; denn für denjenigen, der die Tatsachenzusammenhänge etwas durchschauen kann, hat die ganze Anschauung, daß der Tod kein Wirkliches sei, etwas Ähnliches mit jener Anschauung, die sagt: Die Kälte ist doch nichts Wirkliches, sondern sie ist nur die Herabminderung der Wärme, ist nur eine geringere Wärme; da die Kälte nichts Wirkliches ist, ziehe ich mir keinen Winterrock im Winter an, denn ich werde mich doch nicht gegen etwas Unwirkliches schützen. — Aber davon wollen wir ganz absehen, wir wollen vielmehr den Streit zwischen Alkuin und dem Griechen rein positiv nehmen und wollen uns fragen, was da eigentlich geschehen ist; denn es ist schon etwas höchst Auffälliges, daß ja nicht diskutiert wird über den Begriff der Erlösung selber, nicht diskutiert wird so, daß gewissermaßen die beiden Persönlichkeiten, der Grieche und der römisch-katholische Theologe, denselben Gesichtspunkt einnehmen, sondern daß der römisch-katholische Theologe den Standpunkt ganz verschiebt, bevor er überhaupt darauf eingeht. Er redet nicht in der Richtung weiter, die er gerade eingeschlagen hat, sondern er bringt das ganze Problem in eine ganz andere Richtung. Er fragt: Ist der Tod etwas Wirkliches oder nicht? - und wendet ein, der Tod sei eben nichts Wirkliches.
Das weist uns von vorneherein darauf hin, daß da zwei Anschauungen zusammenstoßen, die aus ganz verschiedenen Seelenverfassungen herauskommen. Und so ist es auch. Der Grieche dachte gewissermaßen noch fort in der Richtung, die im Griechentum im Grunde genommen erst verglommen war zwischen Plato und Aristoteles. In Plato war noch etwas lebendig von der alten Weisheit der Menschheit, von jener Weisheit, die uns hinüberführt nach dem alten Orient, wo, allerdings in alten Zeiten, eine Urweisheit gelebt hat, die dann immer mehr und mehr in die Dekadenz gekommen ist. Die letzten Ausläufer, möchte ich sagen, dieser orientalischen Urweisheit, finden wir bei Plato, wenn wir ihn richtig verstehen können. Dann setzt, wie durch eine rasch sich entwickelnde Metamorphose, der Aristotelismus ein, der im Grunde genommen eine ganz andere Seelenverfassung darbietet, als es die platonische ist. Der Aristotelismus stellt ein ganz anderes Element dar in der Menschheitsentwickelung als der Platonismus. Und wenn wir den Aristotelismus dann weiter verfolgen, so nimmt er auch wiederum verschiedene Formen, verschiedene Metamorphosen an, aber sie lassen sich doch alle in ihrer Ähnlichkeit erkennen. Wir sehen dann, wie als altes Erbgut in dem Griechen, der gegen Alkuin zu kämpfen hat, der Platonismus weiter fortlebt, wie aber bei Alkuin bereits der Aristotelismus vorhanden ist. Und wir werden hingewiesen, indem diese beiden Menschen in unser Blickfeld treten, auf jenes Wechselspiel, das sich vollzogen hat auf europäischem Boden zwischen zwei, man kann nicht einmal gut sagen Weltanschauungen, sondern menschlichen Seelenverfassungen, derjenigen, die ihren Ursprung noch hat in alten Zeiten des Orients drüben und derjenigen, die sich dann später hineinstellt, die wir im Orient noch nicht finden, die auftauchte in den mittleren Gegenden der Zivilisation, die Aristoteles zuerst ergriffen hat. Sie klingt in Aristoteles aber erst leise an; denn in ihm lebt doch noch viel Griechentum, sie entwickelt sich aber dann mit besonderer Vehemenz in der römischen Kultur, innerhalb welcher sie sich schon lange vor Aristoteles, ja vor Plato vorbereitet hat. So daß wir auch sehen, wie auf der italienischen Halbinsel schon seit dem 8. vorchristlichen Jahrhundert sich eine besondere Kultur, nur nuanciert, vorbereitet neben dem, was auf der griechischen Halbinsel weiterlebt wie eine Art letzter Ausläufer der orientalischen Seelenverfassung. Und wenn wir auf die Unterschiede dieser beiden menschlichen Denkweisen eingehen, so finden wir wichtige historische Impulse. Denn dasjenige, was sich in diesen Denkweisen ausdrückt, ging dann über in das Gefühlsleben der Menschen, ging über in die Struktur der menschlichen Handlungen und so weiter.
Nun fragen wir uns einmal: Was lebte denn in dem, was in Urzeiten sich entwickelte im Oriente drüben als Weltanschauung, was dann im Platonismus, ja sogar noch im Neuplatonismus als in einem Spätling seine Ausläufer fand. Es ist eine hochgeistige Kultur, die aus einer inneren Anschauung kam, welche vorzugsweise in Bildern, in Imaginationen lebte, aber in Bildern, die nicht durchdrungen waren von dem Vollbewußtsein, noch nicht durchdrungen waren von dem vollen Ich-Bewußtsein der Menschen. In gewaltigen Bildern ging gerade im alten orientalischen Geistesleben, von dem Veda und Vedanta die Nachklänge sind, dasjenige auf, was eben im Menschen als das Geistige lebt. Aber es war in einer — ich bitte, das Wort nicht mißzuverstehen und es nicht mit dem gewöhnlichen Träumen zu verwechseln —, es war in einer traumhaften, in einer dumpfen Art vorhanden, so daß dieses Seelenleben nicht durchwellt und durchstrahlt war von dem, was im Menschen lebt, wenn er deutlich sich seines Ich und seiner eigenen Wesenheit bewußt wird. Der Orientale war sich wohl bewußt, daß seine Wesenheit vorhanden war vor der Geburt, daß sie durch den Tod wiederum in dieselbe geistige Welt zieht, in der sie vor der Geburt oder vor der Empfängnis vorhanden war. Der Orientale schaute auf dasjenige, was durch Geburten und Tode zog. Aber jenes innere Fühlen, das in dem «Ich bin» lebt, das schaute der Orientale als solches nicht an. Es war gewissermaßen dumpf, wie ausgeflossen in einer Gesamtseelenanschauung, die sich nicht bis zu einem solchen Punkte hin konzentriert, wie es das Ich-Erlebnis ist. In was schaute denn da der Orientale eigentlich hinein, wenn er sein instinktives Schauen hatte?
Man kann es noch fühlen, wie ganz anders diese orientalische Seelenverfassung war als die der späteren Menschheit, wenn man sich zu diesem Verständnis, vielleicht durch Geisteswissenschaft vorbereitet, in jene merkwürdigen Schriften vertieft, die zugeschrieben werden ich will jetzt die Autorfrage nicht weiter untersuchen, ich habe mich öfter darüber ausgesprochen - dem Dionysius vom Areopag, dem Areopagiten. Da wird noch gesprochen von dem «Nichts» als von einer Realität, der nur das Sein der äußeren Welt, wie man sie im gewöhnlichen Bewußtsein überblickt, als etwas anderes Reales entgegengestellt wird. Dieses Sprechen von dem Nichts, das klingt dann noch weiter fort. Bei Scotus Erigena, der am Hofe Karls des Kahlen lebte, findet man noch Nachklänge, und den letzten Nachklang findet man dann im 15. Jahrhundert bei Nikolaus Cusanus. Aber dann verglimmt das vollständig, was gemeint war in dem Nichts, das man bei Dionysius dem Areopagiten findet, von dem aber der Orientale als von etwas ihm Selbstverständlichen sprach. Was war für den Orientalen dieses Nichts? Es war ein Wirkliches für ihn. Er richtete den Blick in die umgebende Sinneswelt, er sagte sich: Diese Sinneswelt ist ausgedehnt im Raum, verfließt in der Zeit, und man sagt im gewöhnlichen Leben zu dem, was im Raume ausgedehnt ist und in der Zeit verfließt, es sei ein Etwas.
Aber das, was der Orientale sah, was für ihn eine Realität war, die durch Geburten und Tode geht, das war nicht in diesem Raum enthalten, in dem sich die Mineralien befinden, die Pflanzen sich entwickeln, die Tiere sich bewegen, der Mensch als physisches Wesen sich bewegt und handelt, es war auch nicht in jener Zeit enthalten, in der sich unsere Vorstellungen, Gefühle und Willensimpulse abspielen. Der Orientale war sich ganz klar: Man muß aus diesem Raume herausgehen, in dem die physischen Dinge ausgedehnt sind, und sich bewegen, und man muß aus dieser Zeit herausgehen, in der unsere Seelenkräfte des gewöhnlichen Lebens sich betätigen. Man muß in eine ganz andere Welt eindringen, in die Welt, die für das äußere zeitlich-räumliche Dasein das Nichts ist, das aber doch ein Wirkliches ist. Der Orientale empfand eben gegenüber den Welterscheinungen etwas, was der Europäer höchstens noch auf dem Gebiete der realen Zahl empfindet. Wenn der Europäer fünfzig Franken hat, so hat er etwas. Wenn er fünfundzwanzig Franken davon ausgibt, so hat er nur noch fünfundzwanzig Franken; wenn er wieder fünfzehn Franken ausgibt, so hat er noch zehn; wenn er diese auch ausgibt, hat er nichts; wenn er jetzt mit Ausgeben weiterfährt, hat er fünf, zehn, fünfzehn, fünfundzwanzig Franken Schulden. Er hat immer nichts, aber er hat doch etwas sehr Reales, wenn er statt einfach leerem Portemonnaie fünfundzwanzig oder fünfzig Franken Schulden hat. Das bedeutet in der realen Welt auch etwas sehr Reales, wenn man diese Schulden hat. Es ist ein Unterschied in der ganzen Lebenssituation, ob man nichts hat oder ob man fünfzig Franken Schulden hat. Diese fünfzig Franken Schulden sind ebenso wirksame Kräfte für die Lebenssituation, wie auf der anderen Seite im entgegengesetzten Sinne fünfzig Franken Vermögen wirksame Kräfte sind. Auf diesem Gebiete läßt sich wahrscheinlich der Europäer auf die Realität der Schulden ein, denn es muß in der realen Welt immer etwas vorhanden sein, wenn man Schulden hat. Die Schulden, die man selber hat, mögen für einen eine noch so sehr negative Größe sein, für den anderen, dem man sie schuldet, sind sie aber eine recht positive Größe.
Also, wenn es nicht bloß auf das Individuum ankommt, sondern auf die Welt, dann ist dasjenige, was ja nach der einen Seite der Null liegt, die entgegengesetzt ist der Vermögensseite, doch etwas sehr Reales. Der Orientale empfand, aber nicht, weil er irgendwie spekulierte, sondern weil ihn seine Anschauung nötigte, so zu empfinden, er empfand: Da erlebe ich auf der einen Seite den Raum und die Zeit, und auf der anderen Seite erlebe ich dasjenige, was nicht im Raum und in der Zeit beobachtet werden kann, was für die Raum- und Zeitdinge und für das Raum- und Zeitgeschehen ein Nichts ist, aber eine Realität ist, eben nur eine andere Realität. Nur durch ein Mißverständnis ist dann dasjenige entstanden, dem sich die abendländische Zivilisation unter Roms Führung hingegeben hat: die Schöpfung der Welt aus dem Nichts, wobei man unter dem Nichts nur die Null gedacht hat. Im Oriente, wo diese Dinge ursprünglich konzipiert worden sind, entsteht die Welt nicht aus dem Nichts, sondern aus jenem Realen, auf das ich Sie eben hingewiesen habe. Und ein Nachklang desjenigen, das durch alle orientalische Denkweise und bis zu Plato herunter vibriert hat, was Ewigkeitsimpuls einer alten Weltanschauung war, ein Nachklang davon lebte in dem Griechen am Hofe Karls des Großen, der mit Alkuin zu diskutieren hatte. Und eine Abweisung des geistigen Lebens, für das dieses Nichts die äußere Form war im Oriente, lebte bei dem Theologen Alkuin, der daher, als der Grieche von dem Tod, der aus dem geistigen Leben heraus verursacht ist, als von etwas Realem sprach, nur erwidern konnte: Der Tod ist doch ein Nichts, also kann er kein Lösegeld erhalten.
Sehen Sie, all das, was Gegensatz ist zwischen alter orientalischer, bis zu Plato reichender Denkweise und dem, was später folgte, drückt sich aus in diesem prägnanten Punkte, wo Alkuin mit dem Griechen am Hofe Karls des Großen diskutierte. Denn, was war mittlerweile eingezogen in die europäische Zivilisation seit Plato, namentlich durch die Verbreitung des romanischen Wesens? Es war eingezogen diejenige Denkweise, welche man dadurch zu begreifen hat, daß sie vorzugsweise auf das geht, was der Mensch durchlebt zwischen Geburt und Tod. Die Seelenverfassung, die sich vorzugsweise beschäftigt mit dem, was der Mensch durchlebt zwischen Geburt und Tod, das ist die logisch-juristische, die logisch dialektisch-juristische. Das Morgenland hatte nichts Logisch-Dialektisches und am wenigsten etwas Juristisches. Das Abendland brachte in die morgenländische Denkweise das logisch-juristische Denken so stark hinein, daß wir selbst das religiöse Empfinden durchjuristet finden. Wir sehen in der Sixtinischen Kapelle in Rom uns entgegenragen von der Meisterhand Michelangelos den Weltenrichter Christus, der da richtet über die Guten und die Bösen.
In die Gedanken über den Weltverlauf ist Juristisch-Dialektisches hineingezogen. Ganz fremd war das der orientalischen Denkweise. Da gab es so etwas nicht, wie Schuld und Sühne, wie Erlösung überhaupt. Daher kann der Grieche fragen: Was ist denn diese Erlösung? — Da gab es eben die Anschauung jener Metamorphose, durch die sich das Ewige umgestaltet durch Geburten und Tode hin; da gab es dasjenige, was in dem Begriff des Karma lebte. Dann aber wurde alles hereingespannt in eine Anschauungsweise, welche eigentlich nur gültig ist für das Leben zwischen Geburt und Tod, welche nur umfassen kann dieses Leben zwischen Geburt und Tod. Das aber, dieses Leben zwischen Geburt und Tod, hatte sich gerade wieder dem Orientalen entzogen. Er blickte viel mehr auf des Menschen Wesenskern hin. Er hatte weniger Verständnis für das, was sich zwischen Geburt und Tod abspielte. Und innerhalb dieser abendländischen Kultur wurde nun groß jene Denkweise, die vorzugsweise das erfaßt, was innerhalb von Geburt und Tod sich abspielt durch jene Kräfte, die der Mensch dadurch hat, daß er sein Geistig-Seelisches mit einem Leib umkleider hat, mit einem physischen und ätherischen Leibe. In dieser Konstitution, in dem innerlichen Erleben des Geistig-Seelischen und in der Art dieses Erlebens, die davon herkommt, daß man eben eingetaucht ist mit dem Geistig-Seelischen in einen physischen Leib, kommt die klare, die volle Erfassung, die innerliche Erfassung des Ich. Daher geschieht es auch im Abendlande, daß der Mensch sich gedrängt fühlt, gerade sein Ich zu erfassen, sein Ich als Göttliches zu erfassen. Wir sehen diesen Drang, das Ich als ein Göttliches zu erfassen, auftreten bei den mittelalterlichen Mystikern, bei Eckart, bei Tauler, bei den anderen. Diese Erfassung des Ich kristallisiert sich mit aller Macht heraus in dem, was die mittlere Kultur ist. So daß wir unterscheiden können: die Ostkultur, die Zeit, in der das Ich erst dumpf erlebt wird; die Mittelkultur, sie ist vorzugsweise diejenige, in der das Ich erlebt wird. Und wir sehen, wie in den mannigfaltigsten Metamorphosen dieses Ich erlebt wird: erst, ich möchte sagen, in jener dämmerhaften Weise, in der es auftritt bei Eckart, bei Tauler, bei den anderen Mystikern; dann immer deutlicher und deutlicher, indem sich alles dasjenige herausentwickelt, was aus dieser Ich-Kultur stammen kann.
Wir sehen dann, wie innerhalb der Ich-Kultur der Mitte ein anderer Einschlag auftritt. Am Ende des 18. Jahrhunderts tritt in Kant etwas auf, was im Grunde genommen gar nicht erklärbar ist aus dem Fortströmen dieser Ich-Kultur. Denn, was kommt durch Kant herauf? Kant untersucht das Erkennen der Natur. Er kommt nicht zurecht damit. Es fällt ihm das Naturerkennen auseinander in Subjektivitäten, er dringt nicht bis zum Ich vor, trotzdem er fortwährend vom Ich spricht, sogar aus dem Ich heraus in manchen Kategorien, in den Anschauungen von Raum und Zeit, die ganze Natur umfassen möchte. Er dringt doch nicht zum wirklichen Erleben des Ich vor. Er konstruiert auch eine praktische Philosophie mit dem kategorischen Imperativ, der aus unergründlichen Gegenden der Menschenseele sich kundgeben soll. Wiederum erscheint dabei nicht das Ich. In der Kantschen Philosophie ist es merkwürdig: Es ist die ganze Wucht der Dialektik, des dialektisch-logisch-juristischen Denkens da, indem alles auf das Ich hintendiert; aber er kann nicht dazu kommen, dieses Ich philosophisch wirklich zu durchschauen. Da muß irgend etwas sein, was ihn daran hindert. Dann kommt Fichte, der noch der Schüler Kants ist, und der mit aller Wucht seine ganze Philosophie aus diesem Ich herausquellen lassen will, der den, ich möchte sagen, durch seine Einfachheit niederschlagenden Satz als den höchsten Satz seiner Philosophie hinstellt: «Ich bin.» Und aus diesem «Ich bin» soll alles, was richtig wissenschaftlich ist, folgen. Man soll gleichsam deduzieren können, herauslesen können aus dem «Ich bin», die ganze Weltanschauung. Kant kann nicht zu dem «Ich bin» kommen. Fichte, gleich hinterher, noch als der Schüler Kants, schleudert ihm entgegen das «Ich bin». Und die Leute sind erstaunt: Das ist ein Schüler Kants, der redet so etwas! — Und Fichte sagt: So viel er verstehen könne, müsste Kant, wenn er richtig zu Ende denken könnte, dasselbe denken, was er denkt! — So unerklärlich ist es Fichte, daß Kant anders denkt als er, daß er sagt: Wenn Kant nur zu Ende denkt, so muß er geradeso denken, so muß er auch zu dem «Ich bin» kommen. — Und Fichte drückt das noch deutlicher aus, indem er sagt: Ich würde lieber die ganze Kantsche Kritik für ein blindes Spiel von zufällig durcheinander gewirbelten Begriffen halten, als für das Werk eines Kopfes, wenn nicht meine Philosophie aus der Kantschen richtig folgen würde. - Kant weist das selbstverständlich zurück. Er will nichts zu tun haben mit dem, was Fichte als seine Konsequenzen gezogen hat.
Nun sehen wir, wie sich an Fichte das anschließt, was dann als deutsche idealistische Philosophie in Schelling, in Hegel aufgesprossen ist, was all die Kämpfe hervorgerufen hat, von denen ich zum Teil in meinen Vorträgen über die Grenzen der Naturerkenntnis gesprochen habe. Aber wir sehen doch etwas Eigentümliches. Wir sehen, wie Hegel ganz in einer kristallklaren Ausgestaltung des Juristisch-DialektischLogischen lebt und ein Weltanschauungsbild daraus gewinnt, aber nur ein Weltanschauungsbild, welches sich interessiert für dasjenige, was zwischen Geburt und Tod verfließt. Denn gehen Sie die ganze Hegelsche Philosophie durch, Sie finden darin nichts, was über Geburt und Tod hinausgeht. Es schließt alles mit der Weltgeschichte, mit Religion, Kunst und Wissenschaft, mit all dem, was hereinfällt in die Erlebnisse zwischen Geburt und Tod.
Was ist denn da Merkwürdiges geschehen? Nun, dasjenige, was in Fichte, Schelling und Hegel herausgekommen ist, diese stärkste Entfaltung der mittleren Kultur, in der das Ich zum vollen Bewußtsein, zum inneren Erleben kam, das war nur eine Reaktion noch, ein letztes Reagieren gegenüber etwas anderem. Denn man versteht Kant nur, wenn man folgendes richtig ins Auge faßt. Jetzt komme ich wieder an einen prägnanten Punkt, von dem sich vieles ableiten läßt. Sehen Sie, Kant war noch - das geht aus seinen älteren Schriften klar hervor — ein Schüler des Rationalismus des 18. Jahrhunderts, der in Leibniz in genialer, in Wolff in pedantischer Weise gelebt hat. Und man sieht: Diesem Rationalismus kam es eigentlich gar nicht darauf an, auf ein Geistig-Wirkliches wirklich zu kommen - Kant wies es daher ab, dieses «Ding an sich», wie er es nannte -, sondern es kam ihm darauf an, zu beweisen, sicher zu beweisen! Kants Schriften sind in dieser Beziehung auch merkwürdig. Er schrieb seine «Kritik der reinen Vernunft», in der er eigentlich fragt: Wie muß die Welt sein, damit man in ihr beweisen kann? — Nicht: Was sind die Realitäten dabei? -, sondern er frägt eigentlich: Wie muß ich mir die Welt denken, damit ich in ihr logisch-dialektisch, logisch beweisen kann? — Es kommt ihm nur darauf an, und er sucht in seinen «Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können», eine Metaphysik zu dem, was sich in seinem Sinne beweisen läßt: Alles andere raus! Hol’ der Teufel die Realität der Welt, man lasse mir nur die Kunst des Beweisens! Was schert mich, was die Wirklichkeit ist; wenn ich sie nicht beweisen kann, dann kümmere ich mich nicht um sie!
In dieser Weise haben diejenigen natürlich nicht gedacht, die solche Bücher geschrieben haben wie Christian Wolff zum Beispiel, «Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt» etwa, sondern ihnen kam es darauf an, ein sauberes, in sich geschlossenes System von Beweisen zu haben, wie sie eben das Beweisen ansehen. Kant lebte in dieser Sphäre; aber da war immerhin etwas da, was zwar ein ausgepreßter Balg der mittleren Weltanschauung war, aber doch in die mittlere Weltanschauung hineinpaßte. Kant aber, der hat noch etwas anderes, was unerklärlich macht, wodurch er Fichtes Lehrer werden konnte. Er regt doch immerhin Fichte an, und Fichte wirft ihm wieder entgegen die starke Betonung des «Ich bin», wirft ihm entgegen allerdings nicht bloße Beweise, denn die wird man bei Fichte nicht suchen, aber ein vollentwickeltes inneres Seelenleben. Es taucht bei Fichte mit aller Kraft des inneren Seelenlebens eigentlich das auf, was man bei den Wolffianern, bei den Leibnizianern strohern finden kann. Fichte konstruiert seine Philosophie aus dem «Ich bin» heraus in lauter reinen Begriffen; nur sind sie bei ihm lebensvoll. Sie sind auch bei Schelling, sie sind auch bei Hegel. Aber was ist denn da eigentlich über Kant herüber geschehen? Nun, man trifft auf den prägnanten Punkt, wenn man Kant verfolgt, wie er sich entwickelt hat. Aus einem Schüler Wolffs ist etwas anderes dadurch geworden, daß ihn der englische Philosoph David Hume, wie er selber sagt, aus dem dumpf-apathischen Schlummer geweckt hat. Was ist da in Kant hineingefahren, was Fichte nicht mehr verstehen konnte? Da ist in Kant - es paßte nur schlecht in ihn hinein, weil er zu stark verstrickt war mit dem Mitteleuropäertum — hineingefahren dasjenige, was jetzt die Westkultur ist. Ihm trat sie entgegen in der Persönlichkeit des David Hume; da fuhr in Kant die Westkultur hinein. Und worin können wir ihr Eigentümliches suchen? In der morgenländischen Kultur, da finden wir, daß das Ich unten dumpf noch lebt, wie traumhaft, in den Seelenerlebnissen, die sich imaginativ bildhaft ausdrücken, ausbreiten. In der Westkultur, da finden wir, daß das Tafel 3
Ich gewissermaßen von den rein äußerlichen Tatsachen erdrückt wird. Da ist das Ich zwar vorhanden, da ist es aber nicht dumpf vorhanden, sondern da bohrt es sich hinein in die Tatsachen. Und da bildet man zum Beispiel eine merkwürdige Psychologie aus. Da redet man nicht so wie Fichte über das Seelenleben, der alles aus dem einen Punkt des Ich herausarbeiten möchte, da redet man von Gedanke und Gedanke und Gedanke, und diese assoziieren sich. Da redet man von Gefühlen und Vorstellungen und Empfindungen, und diese assoziieren sich, und auch Willensimpulse assoziieren sich. Da redet man von dem inneren Seelenleben so, wie von Gedanken, die sich assoziieren.
Fichte redet von dem Ich; das strahlt die Gedanken aus. Im Westen fällt das Ich vollständig heraus, weil es absorbiert, aufgesogen ist von den Gedanken, von den Empfindungen, die man wie selbständig macht, und die sich assoziieren und wieder trennen. Und man verfolgt das Seelenleben so, als ob sich die Vorstellungen verbinden und trennen würden. Lesen Sie Spencer, lesen Sie John Stuart Mill, lesen Sie die amerikanischen Philosophen: überall, wo sie auf Psychologie zu reden kommen, da ist diese merkwürdige Anschauung, die nicht das Ich ausschließt wie der Orient, weil es dort dumpf entwickelt wird, sondern die das Ich voll in Anspruch nimmt, aber es versinken läßt in die Region des vorstellenden, fühlenden, wollenden Seelenlebens. Man könnte sagen: Beim Orientalen ist das Ich noch über Vorstellen, Fühlen und Wollen; es ist noch nicht heruntergestiegen auf das Niveau von Vorstellen, Fühlen und Wollen. Bei dem Menschen der Westkultur ist das Ich schon unter der Sphäre, da ist es unter der Oberfläche von Denken, Fühlen und Wollen, so daß es zunächst nicht mehr bemerkt wird und man von Denken, Fühlen und Wollen wie von selbständigen Mächten redet. - Das ist in Kant hineingefahren in der Gestalt der Philosophie des David Hume. Dem hat sich noch die mittlere Partie der Erdenkultur mit aller Gewalt entgegengestellt in Fichte, in Schelling, in Hegel. Dann überflutet mit dem Darwinismus, mit dem Spencerismus die Westkultur alles, was zunächst da ist.

Nur dann wird man zu einem Verständnisse desjenigen kommen können, was da lebt in der Menschheitsentwickelung, wenn man diese tieferen Kräfte untersucht. Dann findet man, daß sich auf eine naturgemäße Weise im Oriente etwas entwickelt, was eigentlich nur Geistesleben war. Da hat sich in dem mittleren Gebiete etwas entwickelt, was dialektisch-juristisch war, was eigentlich die Staatsidee hervorgebracht hat, weil es auf diese anwendbar ist. Gerade solche Denker, wie Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, konstruieren mit einer ungeheuren Sympathie die einheitlichen Staatsgebilde. Dann taucht aber im Westen eine solche Kultur auf, die von einer Seelenverfassung herrührt, wo das Ich absorbiert ist, unter dem Niveau von Denken, Fühlen und Wollen verläuft, wo man von Assoziationen spricht im Vorstellungs-, im Gefühlsleben. Man sollte dieses Denken nur auf das Wirtschaftsleben anwenden! Da ist es am richtigen Platze. Man war vollständig fehlgegangen, als man es anwendete zuerst auf etwas anderes als auf das Wirtschaftsleben. Da ist es groß, da ist es genial, und würde Spencer, würde John Stuart Mill, würde David Hume, würden sie alle dasjenige, was sie auf die Philosophie verschwendet haben, auf Einrichtungen des Wirtschaftslebens verwendet haben, es wäre großartig geworden. Würden die in Mitteleuropa wohnenden Menschen das, was ihnen als Begabung naturgemäß war, beschränkt haben auf den bloßen Staat, und würden sie nicht zugleich damit auch das Geistesleben und das Wirtschaftsleben haben erfassen wollen, es hätte etwas Großartiges daraus werden können. Denn mit dem, was Hegel denken konnte, was Fichte denken konnte, hätte man, wenn man innerhalb des juristisch-staatlichen Gebildes bliebe, das wir im dreigliedrigen Organismus heraussondern wollen als das staatliche Gebilde, etwas Großartiges erreichen können. Aber dadurch, daß diesen Geistern vorschwebte, sie müßten ein Staatsgebilde schaffen, wo das Wirtschaftsleben drinnen ist und das Geistesleben drinnen ist, dadurch wurden Karikaturen statt wirklicher Staatsgebilde. Und das Geistesleben hat man überhaupt nur gehabt als ein Erbgut des alten Orientes. Man wußte nur nicht, daß man noch von diesem Erbgut des alten Orientes lebte. Was zum Beispiel brauchbare Aufstellungen der christlichen Theologie sind, ja, was brauchbare Aufstellungen noch innerhalb unserer materialistischen Wissenschaften sind, es ist entweder altes orientalisches Erbgut, oder es ist ein Wechselbalg von juristisch-dialektischem Denken, oder es ist schon herübergenommen, so wie Spencer und Mill es getan haben, aus der westlichen Kultur, die für das Wirtschaftsleben besonders geeignet ist.
So war über die Erde hin verteilt geistiges Denken, das der alte Orient hatte, aber in einer instinktiven Weise, wie es heute nicht mehr zu gebrauchen ist, da es heute in der Dekadenz ist, dialektisch-staatliches Denken, das seine Auflösung erlebte gerade durch die Weltkatastrophe. Denn niemand war weniger geeignet, wirtschaftlich zu denken, als die Schüler von Fichte, Schelling und Hegel. Als sie anfingen, ein Reich zu gründen, das vorzugsweise durch die Wirtschaft groß werden wollte, mußten sie selbstverständlich unterliegen, denn das war nicht naturgemäß in ihrer Begabung gelegen. Verteilt war nach dem historischen Entwickelungsgang der Menschheit: geistiges Denken, staatlich-politisches Denken, wirtschaftliches Denken auf Osten, Mitte, Westen. Wir sind an dem Punkte der menschlichen Entwickelung angelangt, wo über die ganze Menschheit Verständnis, gleichermaßen Verständnis sich ausbreiten muß. Wie kann das geschehen?
Das kann nur geschehen aus der Initiationskultur, aus der neuen Geisteswissenschaft heraus, die nun nicht nach Einseitigkeiten hin sich entwickelt, sondern die gerade auf allen Gebieten das, was sich sonst von selber dreigegliedert hat, als Dreigliederung auch im sozialen Leben wirklich ins Auge faßt, die zusammenfaßt dasjenige, was über die Erde verbreitet ist. Diese kann aber nicht durch natürliche Anlagen verbreitet werden, sie kann nur dadurch verbreitet werden, daß man sich einläßt auf diejenigen, die diese Dinge durchschauen, die wirklich erleben können als ein besonderes Gebiet das Geistgebiet, als ein besonderes Gebiet das Staats- oder politische Gebiet, als ein besonderes Gebiet das Wirtschaftsgebiet. Darin liegt die Einigung der Menschen über die Erde hin, daß dasjenige, was auf drei Sphären verteilt war, im Menschen zusammengefaßt wird, indem er es selbst im sozialen Organismus so gliedert, daß es sich vor ihm, vor seiner Nase, in Harmonie befinden kann. Das aber kann nur erfolgen aus der geisteswissenschaftlichen Schulung heraus. Und hier stehen wir an dem Punkte, wo wir sagen müssen: Wir sehen in alten Zeiten die einzelnen Persönlichkeiten, wir sehen sie aussprechen dasjenige, was der Geist der Zeit ist. Aber wenn wir wirklich prüfen, zum Beispiel gerade innerhalb der orientalischen Kultur, dann finden wir, daß im Grunde genommen in den Massen instinktiv lebte etwas von Seelenverfassung, was in einer merkwürdigen, selbstverständlichen Übereinstimmung mit dem war, was die einzelnen aussprachen.
Dieses Zusammenwirken wird aber immer geringer und geringer. In unserer Zeit sehen wir das entgegengesetzte Extrem sich herausbilden. Wir sehen in den Massen die entgegengesetzten Instinkte von dem heraufkommen, was der Menschheit eigentlich heilsam ist. Wir sehen heraufkommen, was gerade das notwendig macht, was dem Einzelnen, der auf die Geisteswissenschaft bis in ihre Tiefen eingehen kann, entströmen kann. Aus den Instinkten wird kein Heil kommen, allein aus jenem Verständnis, von dem hier auch Dr. Unger gesprochen hat, das oftmals betont wird, das jeder Mensch dem Geistesforscher entgegenbringen kann, wenn er sich nur dem gesunden Menschenverstand wirklich hingibt. So wird eine Kultur kommen, wo gerade die einzelne Individualität mit ihrem immer tieferen Eindringen in innere Tiefen der geistigen Welten von besonderer Wichtigkeit ist, und wo man den, der so eindringt in die geistigen Welten, gelten lassen will wie den, der sonst ein Handwerk betreibt. Man läßt sich nicht vom Schneider Stiefel machen, nicht vom Schuster rasieren, warum sollte man das, was man braucht als Weltanschauung, bei jemandem anderen holen als bei dem, der in sie eingeweiht ist? Aber das ist es ja, was gerade gegenwärtig im intensivsten Sinne notwendig ist zum Menschenheil, obwohl die Reaktion dagegen da ist, die zeigt, wie die Menschheit sich noch sträubt gegen das, was ihr heilsam ist. Das ist der furchtbare Kampf, der Ernst, in dem wir drinnenstehen.
Keiner Zeit ist notwendiger gewesen, daß hingehorcht werde auf das, was der Einzelne in dem oder jenem weiß, und daß - nicht auf Autoritätsglaube hin, sondern auf Verstand und auf verständnismäßige Zustimmung hin — wirken kann für das soziale Leben derjenige, der auf einem einzelnen Gebiete etwas weiß. Aber die Instinkte wenden sich zunächst dagegen, und man glaubt, daß man vom allgemeinen Nivellement aus irgend etwas Heilsames erreichen kann. Das ist der ernste Kampf, in dem wir drinnenstehen. Da hilft keine Sympathie und Antipathie, da hilft kein Leben in Schlagworten, da hilft nur ein klares Ansehen der Tatsachen. Denn heute entscheiden sich ja die großen Fragen, die Fragen, ob die Persönlichkeit oder die Masse eine Bedeutung hat. Für andere Zeiten hatte sie keine große Bedeutung, denn es stimmte die Masse mit den einzelnen Persönlichkeiten zusammen; die Persönlichkeiten waren gewissermaßen doch nur die Exponenten der Masse. Immer mehr gehen wir derjenigen Zeit entgegen, wo der Einzelne ganz in sich selber den Quell dessen suchen muß, was er zu finden hat, und was er dann wiederum hineinzuwerfen hat in das soziale Leben, und es ist nur das letzte Sträuben gegen diese Geltung gerade der Individualität und einer immer größeren und größeren Zahl von Individualitäten. Man kann geradezu hineinschauen, wie das, was Geisteswissenschaft zeigt, überall an dem prägnanten Punkt sich auch beweist. Wir reden von den notwendigen Assoziationen im Wirtschaftsleben, brauchen dazu ein bestimmtes Denken. In der Westkultur hat sich das entwickelt, indem man die Gedanken sich assoziieren läßt. Wenn man das nehmen könnte, was John Stuart Mill mit der Logik treibt, wenn man diese Gedanken dort herausnehmen und sie aufs Wirtschaftsleben anwenden könnte, da paßten sie hinein, da kämen gerade die Assoziationen hinein, die nicht hineinpassen in die Psychologie. Bis in dasjenige hinein, was so erscheint im Gebiete der menschlichen Entwickelung, verfolgt Geisteswissenschaft eben die Realität.
Daher steht Geisteswissenschaft mit vollem Bewußtsein in dem ganzen Ernst der gegenwärtigen Weltlage drinnen, sie weiß, welch großer Kampf sich abspielt zwischen dem, was aus der Geisteswissenschaft heraus an sozialen Impulsen in der Dreigliederung kommen kann und demjenigen, was als bolschewistische Welle, die zum Unheile der Menschheit führen würde, sich dieser Dreigliederung entgegenwirft. Und ein Drittes neben diesen beiden gibt es nicht. Zwischen diesen beiden muß sich der Kampf abspielen. Das muß man einsehen. Alles andere ist bereits Dekadentes. Wer unbefangen die Verhältnisse anschaut, in denen wir drinnenstehen, der muß sich schon sagen, daß es heute notwendig ist, daß alle Kräfte zusammengenommen werden, damit diese furchtbare ahrimanische Sache, die sich entgegenwirft der Geisteskultur, abgewehrt werden könne.
Dieser Bau steht da, zunächst unvollendet. Es ist heute aus den Mittelländern heraus nicht dasjenige zu haben, was ihn zum großen Teile bis zu diesem Punkte gebracht hat im Zusammenhange mit dem, was von den neutralen Staaten uns zugekommen ist. Wir müssen Zuschüsse aus den Ländern der ehemaligen Entente haben. Da muß Verständnis entwickelt werden für dasjenige, was eine Einheitskultur werden soll, die Geist und Politik und Wirtschaft enthält. Denn die Menschen müssen aus einer einseitigen Anlage heraus und denjenigen folgen, die auch von Politik und Wirtschaft etwas verstehen, die nicht nur in Dialektik machen, sondern auch Geistiges durchschauen und auf Wirtschaftsimpulse sich einlassen, nicht Staaten gründen wollen, in denen der Staat schon selber wirtschaften könne. Die westlichen Völker werden einsehen müssen, daß zu ihrer besonderen Zukunftsbegabung im wirtschaftlichen Assoziationenwesen, das sie gerade am verkehrten Ende, bei der Psychologie, angebracht haben, zu dem sich hinzuentwickeln muß: ein volles Verständnis des staatlich-politischen Elementes, welches andere Quellen hat als das wirtschaftliche Leben, und des geistigen Elementes zu gewinnen. Aber am Boden liegen die Mittelländer. Man wird in westlichen Gebieten das einsehen müssen - an den Orient ist ja gar nicht zu denken -, was dieser Bau hier will! Daher ist es nötig, daß man sich daraufhin besinnt, wie es geschehen muß, daß für diejenige Kultur wirklich gesorgt werde, die hier jetzt sich zeigen wollte als eine solche Kultur, die berufen ist, das Hochschulwesen der Zukunft zu durchdringen und die sich in der Begründung der Waldorfschule gezeigt hat als eine solche, die das Volksschulwesen durchleuchten kann. Aber wir brauchen dazu die verständnisvolle Unterstützung weitester Kreise.
Wir brauchen dazu vor allen Dingen Mittel. Zu all dem, was im höheren oder niederen Sinne Schule heißt, brauchen wir die Gesinnung, die ich schon betätigte damals, als die Waldorfschule in Stuttgart begründet wurde; bei der Begründung sagte ich es, in der Eröffnungsrede: Diese eine Waldorfschule, ja, schön, daß wir sie haben, aber für sich ist sie nichts; sie ist erst etwas, wenn wir in dem nächsten Vierteljahre zehn solcher Waldorfschulen errichten würden, und dann weitere. Das hat die Welt nicht verstanden, dazu hatte sie kein Geld. Denn da steht sie auf dem Standpunkt: Oh, die Ideale sind zu hoch und zu rein, als daß wir das schmutzige Geld an sie heranbringen sollten; das behalten wir lieber in der Tasche, da ist es am richtigen Platz, das schmutzige Geld. Die Ideale, oh, die sind viel zu rein, die darf man nicht besudeln mit dem Geld! - Es läßt sich allerdings eine solche Verkörperung der Ideale mit derjenigen Reinheit nicht erreichen, an die das schmutzige Geld nicht herangebracht wird, und so müssen wir schon daran denken, daß wir bis Jetzt ja bei der einen Waldorfschule stehen blieben, die eigentlich noch nicht recht vorwärts kann, weil wir in großen Geldsorgen steckten im Herbste. Sie sind zunächst behoben; zu Ostern werden wir wieder davor stehen. Und hier, hier werden wir nach verhältnismäßig kurzer Zeit fragen: Sollen wir aufhören? Und wir werden aufhören müssen, wenn nicht vorher ein sehr stark in die Taschen greifendes Verständnis sich findet.
Daher kommt es darauf an, nach dieser Richtung hin Verständnis zu erwecken. Ich glaube nicht, daß viel Verständnis erwachsen würde — das hat sich uns schon gezeigt -, wenn wir sprechen würden, daß wir etwas wollen für den Bau in Dornach oder dergleichen. Aber — und dafür findet sich ja heute noch Verständnis —, wenn man Sanatorien oder dergleichen gründen will, dazu kriegt man Geld, so viel man will! Das wollen wir ja nicht gerade, wir wollen nicht lauter Sanatorien begründen, sind ganz einverstanden mit ihrer Begründung, soweit sie notwendig sind, aber hier handelt es sich vor allen Dingen um die Pflege derjenigen Geisteskultur, deren Notwendigkeit wohl sich beweisen wird aus dem, was gerade dieser Hochschulkursus hier leisten wollte. Daher versuchte ich dasjenige anzuregen, was ich vor einigen Tagen hier in das Wort zusammengefaßt habe: «Weltschulverein». Unsere deutschen Freunde sind abgereist; auf sie kommt es nicht an bei diesem Weltschulverein. Es kommt auf diejenigen an, die als Freunde zum größten Teil aus allen möglichen Gegenden der nichtdeutschen Welt hier erschienen sind und hier noch sitzen, daß sie verstehen dieses Wort «Weltschulverein», denn es ist notwendig, daß wir Schulen über Schulen in allen Gegenden der Welt aus dem pädagogisch-didaktischen Geiste heraus gründen, der in der Waldorfschule herrscht. Es ist notwendig, daß wir diese Schule erweitern können, bis wir den Anschluß finden an dasjenige, was wir hier als Hochschulwesen wollen. Dazu ist aber notwendig, daß wir imstande sind, diesen Bau mit allem, was zu ihm gehört, zu vollenden und fortwährend dasjenige unterhalten können, was notwendig ist, um hier zu wirken, um zu schaffen, zu schaffen an dem weiteren Ausbau aller einzelnen Wissenschaften aus dem Geiste der Geisteswissenschaft heraus.
Es fragen einen die Leute, wieviel Geld man zu alledem braucht. Man kann gar nicht sagen, wieviel man braucht, denn nach oben hat das überhaupt niemals eine Grenze. Selbstverständlich — einen Weltschulverein, wir werden ihn nicht dadurch begründen, daß wir ein Komitee schaffen von zwölf oder fünfzehn oder dreißig Personen, die schöne Statuten ausarbeiten, wie ein solcher Weltschulverein wirken und arbeiten soll. Das hat alles keinen Zweck. Ich gebe nichts auf Programme, nichts auf Statuten, sondern auf die Arbeit der lebendigen Menschen, die verständnisvoll wirken. Man wird diesen Weltschulverein einmal gründen können, nun, nach London wird man ja noch lange Zeit nicht kommen können; aber vom Haag oder von einem solchen Orte aus, wenn etwa dadurch eine Unterlage geschaffen ist, und noch durch manche andere Dinge, wenn diejenigen Freunde, die jetzt nach Norwegen oder Schweden oder Holland oder nach irgendwelchen anderen Ländern, nach England, Frankreich, Amerika und so weiter gehen, wenn diese Freunde überall, bei jedem Menschen, an den sie herankommen können, die Überzeugung, die wohlbegründete Überzeugung hervorrufen: Einen Weltschulverein muß es geben! — Das müßte wie ein Lauffeuer durch die Welt gehen: Ein Weltschulverein muß entstehen zur Beschaffung der materiellen Mittel für die Geisteskultur, die hier gemeint ist. - Kann man ja sonst als einzelner von allem möglichen Hunderte und Hunderte von Menschen überzeugen, warum sollte man denn nicht in einer kurzen Zeit - denn der Niedergang geht so schnell, daß nur kurze Zeit uns zur Verfügung steht -, als ein einzelner Mensch auf viele wirken können, so daß man, wenn man dann nach einigen Wochen etwa nach dem Haag kommt, sehen würde, wie schon weitverbreitet das Urteil ist: Die Entstehung eines Weltschulvereins ist notwendig, nur die Mittel fehlen zu alledem. Was man von Dornach aus will, ist eine historische Notwendigkeit. -— Dann wird man reden können über die Inaugurierung dieses Weltschulvereins, wenn die Meinung über ihn schon da ist. Komitees zu begründen und den Weltschulverein zu beschließen, das ist utopistisch, das hat gar keinen Zweck; aber von Mensch zu Mensch zu wirken und die Meinung, die begründete Meinung in einer Raschheit zu verbreiten, die eben nötig ist, das ist dasjenige, was vorausgehen muß der Gründung. Geisteswissenschaft lebt in Realitäten. Deshalb läßt sie sich auch nicht auf programmäßiige Vornahmen von Gründungen ein, sondern sie weist auf dasjenige hin, was unter Realitäten — die Menschen sind ja Realität —, was unter Menschen zu geschehen hat, damit eine solche Sache eine Aussicht hat.
Also darauf kommt es an, daß wir endlich lernen von der Geisteswissenschaft, im realen Leben zu stehen. Ich werde mich nie einlassen auf eine bloß utopistische Begründung des Weltschulvereins, sondern ich werde der Meinung immer sein: Der Weltschulverein kann erst entstehen, wenn eine genügend große Anzahl von Menschen von seiner Notwendigkeit überzeugt sind. Und damit dasjenige, was der Menschheit notwendig ist — es hat sich ja wohl aus unseren Hochschulkursen erwiesen —, geschehen könne, dazu muß dieser Weltschulverein gegründet werden. Also man sehe das, was mit diesem Weltschulverein gemeint ist, im ganzen internationalen Leben im rechten Sinne an! In diese Aufforderung möchte ich ausklingen lassen am heutigen Tage dasjenige, was in ganz anderer Weise aus unserem ganzen Kursus heraus zu der Menschheit gesprochen hat gerade durch diejenigen, die hier gewesen sind, und von denen wir die Hoffnung und den Wunsch haben, sie mögen es in die Welt hinaustragen. Der Weltschulverein, er kann die Antwort der Welt sein auf dasjenige, was wie eine Frage vor die Welt hingestellt wird, aber eine Frage, die aus den wirklichen Kräften des Menschenwerdens, das heißt, der Menschheitsgeschichte herausgegriffen ist. Also, was geschehen kann für den Weltschulverein nach jener Überzeugung, die Sie hier haben gewinnen können in den letzten drei Wochen, das geschehe! Darinnen klingt aus dasjenige, was ich auch heute noch habe sagen wollen.
First Lecture
Several things have been mentioned in the lectures given here during the course on history that may be of particular importance to consider at the present time. First of all, with regard to the historical course of human development, the often-discussed question has been raised as to whether the main driving forces in this development are the individual outstanding, influential personalities, or whether the essential is brought about not by these individual personalities but by the masses. This has always been a controversial point in many circles, and the decision has really been made more out of sympathy or antipathy than out of real knowledge. That is one fact that I would like to mention as important, so to speak. The other fact that I would like to note here as important, based on historical considerations, is the following: At the beginning of the 19th century, Wilhelm von Humboldt made a clear statement demanding that history should be viewed in such a way that one should not only consider the individual facts that can be observed externally in the physical world, but that one should use a summarizing, synthesizing power to see what is effective in historical development, which, however, can only be found by those who are, in a certain sense, poetic, but then actually poetic in the sense of summarizing the historical facts in a truthful way. Attention has also been drawn to how, in the course of the 19th century, precisely the opposite historical way of thinking and attitude underwent a special development, how ideas were by no means pursued in history, but only a sense for the external world of facts was developed. And it has been pointed out that it is precisely on the latter question that clarity can only be achieved through the spiritual sciences, because only the spiritual sciences can reveal the real driving forces behind the historical development of humanity. Humboldt did not yet have access to such spiritual science. He spoke of ideas, but ideas have no driving force. Ideas as such are abstractions, as I mentioned here yesterday. And anyone who wants to find ideas as the driving forces of history could never prove that these ideas really do anything, because they are not essential, and only essential things can do anything. The spiritual science points to real spiritual forces that lie behind the sensory-physical facts, and in such real spiritual forces lie the motors of history, even if these spiritual forces must then be expressed for humans through ideas.
But we can only gain clarity about all these things if we take a deeper look at the historical development of humanity from the standpoint of spiritual science, and today we want to do this in such a way that our observations reveal some facts that may be important for assessing the current situation of humanity. I have often mentioned that when spiritual science engages in historical observation, it must actually engage in symptomatology, a symptomatology that consists in being aware that behind the stream of physical and sensory facts lie the driving spiritual forces. But everywhere in historical development there are points where the essential nature symptomatically comes to the surface and where it can be assessed from the appearances, if only one has the opportunity to penetrate more deeply into the depths of historical development through one's knowledge of these appearances.

I would like to clarify this with a simple, sensual drawing. Let us assume that this is a stream of historical facts (see drawing). What are the driving forces actually lies beneath the stream of these facts, as observed by ordinary observation. If, for example, the soul's eye observes this stream of facts, then the actual working of the driving forces would lie beneath the stream of facts (red). But there are significant points within the stream of facts. And these significant points are distinguished by the fact that what is otherwise hidden comes to the surface at these points. So we can say: Here, in a special phenomenon that only needs to be correctly assessed, it becomes clear what is also at work everywhere else, but which is not revealed in such striking phenomena. Let us assume that what is happening here (see drawing) took place in some year of world history, say around 800 AD. What was significant for Europe, let us say for Western Europe, naturally also had an effect before and after that time, but it did not manifest itself in such a striking way in the preceding and following periods as it did at that particular moment. If one points to such a view of history, which looks at concise points, then this is entirely in keeping with Goetheanism. For Goethe wanted to organize all world views in such a way that attention was focused on certain concise points and that the rest of world events could then be understood from what could be seen in these concise points. Goethe says quite explicitly that within the abundance of facts, it is important to find a concise point from which the neighboring areas can be surveyed and from which much can be unraveled.
Now, let us take the year 800, for example. Here we can point to a fact in the development of Western European humanity which, compared to the usual view of history, might seem insignificant, which one might not even consider noteworthy for what we otherwise call history, but which is nevertheless a concise point for a deeper consideration of the development of humanity. Around this year, there was a kind of theological dispute between Alcuin, who was a kind of court philosopher of the Frankish Empire, and a Greek living in the Frankish Empire at the time. The Greek, who was well versed in the particular state of mind of the Greek people, which had been passed down to him, wanted to judge the principles of Christianity and came up with the concept of redemption. He asked the question: To whom was the ransom actually paid in this redemption through Christ Jesus? The Greek thinker came to the conclusion that death was the ransom paid. So it was, in a sense, a kind of theory of redemption that this Greek developed from his entirely Greek way of thinking, which was just becoming acquainted with Christianity. Death was the ransom paid by the powers of the world.
Alcuin, who was part of the theological movement that became decisive for the development of the Roman Catholic Church in the West, discussed what this Greek had put forward in the following way. He said: The ransom can only be paid to a being that is real; but death has no reality, death only ends reality, death is not real; therefore, the ransom could not have been paid to death.
Now, it is not important to criticize Alcuin's way of thinking, for to anyone who can see through the facts, the whole view that death is not real is similar to the view that says: Cold is not real, but only a reduction in warmth, only less warmth; since cold is not real, I do not wear a winter coat in winter, because I am not protecting myself against something unreal. — But let us leave that aside and take the dispute between Alcuin and the Greek at face value and ask ourselves what actually happened; for it is highly remarkable that there is no discussion of the concept of salvation itself, no discussion in which the two personalities, the Greek and the Roman Catholic theologian, take the same point of view, but rather that the Roman Catholic theologian shifts the point of view entirely before even entering into it. He does not continue in the direction he has just taken, but takes the whole problem in a completely different direction. He asks: Is death something real or not? — and objects that death is not something real.
This indicates from the outset that two views are colliding here, views that arise from completely different states of mind. And so it is. The Greek, in a sense, continued to think along the lines that had basically faded away in Greek culture between Plato and Aristotle. In Plato, something of the ancient wisdom of humanity was still alive, that wisdom which leads us back to the ancient Orient, where, admittedly in ancient times, a primordial wisdom lived, which then fell more and more into decadence. The last remnants, I would say, of this oriental primordial wisdom can be found in Plato, if we can understand him correctly. Then, as if through a rapidly developing metamorphosis, Aristotelianism sets in, which basically presents a completely different state of mind than the Platonic one. Aristotelianism represents a completely different element in human development than Platonism. And if we then follow Aristotelianism further, it again takes on various forms, various metamorphoses, but they can all be recognized in their similarity. We then see how, as an old legacy, Platonism lives on in the Greek who has to fight against Alcuin, but how Aristotelianism is already present in Alcuin. And when these two men come into view, we are reminded of the interplay that took place on European soil between two—one cannot even say worldviews, but rather human states of mind—one that has its origins in the ancient times of the Orient, and one that emerged later, which we do not yet find in the Orient, which appeared in the middle regions of civilization and first took hold of Aristotle. However, it only sounds faintly in Aristotle, for there is still much Greek spirit living in him, but it then develops with particular vehemence in Roman culture, within which it had already been preparing long before Aristotle, indeed before Plato. So we can also see how, since the 8th century BC, a special culture has been developing on the Italian peninsula, only in a more nuanced form, alongside what continues to live on the Greek peninsula as a kind of last remnant of the Oriental state of mind. And when we examine the differences between these two ways of thinking, we find important historical impulses. For what is expressed in these ways of thinking then passed into the emotional life of human beings, into the structure of human actions, and so on.
Now let us ask ourselves: What was it that lived in what developed in the Orient in ancient times as a worldview, which then found its offshoots in Platonism, and even in Neoplatonism as a latecomer? It is a highly spiritual culture that came from an inner vision that lived primarily in images, in imaginations, but in images that were not permeated by full consciousness, not yet permeated by the full self-consciousness of human beings. In the ancient Oriental spiritual life, of which the Vedas and Vedanta are echoes, what lives in human beings as the spiritual emerged in powerful images. But it was present in a — please do not misunderstand the word and confuse it with ordinary dreaming — it was present in a dreamlike, dull manner, so that this soul life was not permeated and illuminated by what lives in human beings when they become clearly conscious of their ego and their own essence. The Oriental was well aware that his essence existed before birth, that through death it returns to the same spiritual world in which it existed before birth or before conception. The Oriental looked at that which passed through births and deaths. But the Oriental did not look at that inner feeling that lives in the “I am” as such. It was, in a sense, dull, as if diffused in a general view of the soul that did not concentrate to such a degree as the experience of the self. What did the Oriental actually see when he had his instinctive vision?
One can still feel how completely different this Oriental state of mind was from that of later humanity when, perhaps prepared by spiritual science, one delves into those strange writings attributed to—I will not examine the question of authorship further here, as I have spoken about it often—Dionysius of the Areopagus, the Areopagite. There is still talk of “nothingness” as a reality, which is contrasted with the existence of the external world as we perceive it in ordinary consciousness as something else real. This talk of nothingness continues to resonate. In Scotus Erigena, who lived at the court of Charles the Bald, one finds echoes of this, and the last echo is found in the 15th century in Nicholas of Cusa. But then what was meant in the nothingness found in Dionysius the Areopagite, but which the Oriental spoke of as something self-evident, completely fades away. What was this nothingness for the Oriental? It was real for him. He looked at the sensory world around him and said to himself: This sensory world is extended in space, flows in time, and in ordinary life we say that what is extended in space and flows in time is a something.
But what the Oriental saw, what was a reality for him, passing through births and deaths, was not contained in this space in which minerals exist, plants develop, animals move, and human beings as physical beings move and act; nor was it contained in the time in which our ideas, feelings, and impulses of will take place. The Oriental was quite clear: one must leave this space in which physical things are extended and move, and one must leave this time in which the soul forces of ordinary life are active. One must enter a completely different world, the world that is nothingness for external temporal and spatial existence, but which is nevertheless real. The Oriental felt something toward the phenomena of the world that the European feels at most in the realm of real numbers. If a European has fifty francs, he has something. If he spends twenty-five francs of that, he only has twenty-five francs left; if he spends another fifteen francs, he has ten left; if he spends those too, he has nothing; if he continues spending, he has five, ten, fifteen, twenty-five francs in debt. He still has nothing, but he has something very real if he has twenty-five or fifty francs in debt instead of an empty wallet. In the real world, having this debt also means something very real. There is a difference in one's entire life situation between having nothing and having fifty francs in debt. This fifty-franc debt is just as effective a force in his life as, on the other hand, fifty francs in assets are an effective force in the opposite sense. In this area, Europeans are probably more willing to accept the reality of debt, because in the real world, if you have debts, there must always be something to pay them off with. The debts you owe may be a very negative factor for you, but for the person you owe them to, they are a very positive factor.
So, if it is not just the individual that matters, but the world, then what lies on one side of zero, which is the opposite of the asset side, is something very real. The Oriental felt this, not because he speculated in some way, but because his view compelled him to feel this way. He felt: On the one hand, I experience space and time, and on the other hand, I experience that which cannot be observed in space and time, which is nothing for the things of space and time and for the events of space and time, but which is a reality, just a different reality. It was only through a misunderstanding that what Western civilization under Roman leadership devoted itself to arose: the creation of the world out of nothing, whereby nothing was understood to mean only zero. In the East, where these things were originally conceived, the world does not arise out of nothing, but out of that reality to which I have just referred. And an echo of that which vibrated through all Eastern thought and down to Plato, which was the impulse of eternity in an ancient worldview, lived on in the Greek at the court of Charlemagne, who had to discuss with Alcuin. And a rejection of spiritual life, for which this nothingness was the outer form in the East, lived on in the theologian Alcuin, who, when the Greek spoke of death caused by spiritual life as something real, could only reply: Death is nothing, so it cannot receive a ransom.
You see, everything that is contrary to the ancient Eastern way of thinking, which extended as far as Plato, and what followed later is expressed in this concise point where Alcuin discussed with the Greek at the court of Charlemagne. For what had meanwhile entered European civilization since Plato, namely through the spread of the Roman spirit? It was the way of thinking that can be understood as focusing primarily on what a person experiences between birth and death. The state of mind that is primarily concerned with what a person experiences between birth and death is the logical-legal, the logical-dialectical-legal. The Orient had nothing logical-dialectical and even less legal. The West introduced logical-legal thinking into the Eastern way of thinking to such an extent that we ourselves find even religious sentiment legalistic. In the Sistine Chapel in Rome, we see Christ, the judge of the world, created by the masterful hand of Michelangelo, judging the good and the evil.
Legal-dialectical thinking has been drawn into ideas about the course of the world. This was completely foreign to the Eastern way of thinking. There was no such thing as guilt and atonement, or redemption at all. Hence the Greek can ask: What is this redemption? — There was the view of metamorphosis, through which the eternal is transformed through births and deaths; there was that which lived in the concept of karma. But then everything was forced into a way of looking at things that is actually only valid for life between birth and death, which can only encompass this life between birth and death. But this life between birth and death had just withdrawn from the Oriental. He looked much more at the core of human nature. They had less understanding of what took place between birth and death. And within this Western culture, a way of thinking became prevalent that primarily grasped what takes place within birth and death through those forces that human beings have because they have clothed their spiritual-soul life in a body, in a physical and etheric body. In this constitution, in the inner experience of the spiritual-soul life and in the nature of this experience, which comes from being immersed with the spiritual-soul life in a physical body, comes the clear, full grasp, the inner grasp of the I. This is why it happens in the West that people feel compelled to grasp their ego, to grasp their ego as something divine. We see this urge to grasp the ego as something divine in the medieval mystics, in Eckhart, in Tauler, and in others. This grasp of the I crystallizes with all its power in what is the middle culture. So we can distinguish between the Eastern culture, the time when the I is only dimly experienced, and the middle culture, which is primarily the one in which the I is experienced. And we see how this ego is experienced in the most diverse metamorphoses: first, I would say, in that dim way in which it appears in Eckhart, in Tauler, in the other mystics; then more and more clearly, as everything that can come from this ego culture develops.
We then see how another influence appears within the ego culture of the middle. At the end of the 18th century, something appears in Kant that is basically inexplicable from the continuation of this ego culture. For what emerges through Kant? Kant investigates the knowledge of nature. He cannot come to terms with it. His understanding of nature falls apart into subjectivities; he does not penetrate to the ego, even though he constantly speaks of the ego, even from the ego in some categories, in his views of space and time, which seek to encompass the whole of nature. He does not penetrate to the real experience of the ego. He also constructs a practical philosophy with the categorical imperative, which is supposed to manifest itself from the unfathomable depths of the human soul. Again, the self does not appear. In Kant's philosophy, it is strange: the whole force of dialectic, of dialectical-logical-legal thinking is there, in that everything tends toward the self; but he cannot bring himself to truly see through this self philosophically. There must be something that prevents him from doing so. Then comes Fichte, who is still Kant's student, and who wants to let his entire philosophy spring forth from this ego with all its force, who presents the sentence, which I would say is striking in its simplicity, as the highest sentence of his philosophy: “I am.” And from this “I am” everything that is scientifically correct is supposed to follow. One should be able to deduce, as it were, to read out of the “I am” the entire worldview. Kant cannot arrive at the “I am.” Fichte, right behind him, still as Kant's student, hurls the “I am” at him. And people are astonished: this is a student of Kant, talking like this! — And Fichte says: as far as he can understand, Kant, if he could think things through properly, would have to think the same as he does! — It is so inexplicable to Fichte that Kant thinks differently from him that he says: if Kant only thinks things through to their conclusion, he must think exactly the same, he must also arrive at “I am.” — And Fichte expresses this even more clearly by saying: I would rather consider the whole of Kant's critique to be a blind game of randomly jumbled concepts than the work of a mind, if my philosophy did not follow correctly from Kant's. — Kant naturally rejects this. He wants nothing to do with what Fichte has drawn as his conclusions.
Now we see how this connects with Fichte, which then sprouted as German idealistic philosophy in Schelling and Hegel, which caused all the struggles I have discussed in part in my lectures on the limits of knowledge of nature. But we see something peculiar. We see how Hegel lives entirely in a crystal-clear elaboration of the legal-dialectical-logical and derives a worldview from it, but only a worldview that is interested in what flows between birth and death. For if you go through the whole of Hegel's philosophy, you will find nothing in it that goes beyond birth and death. It ends with world history, with religion, art, and science, with everything that falls within the experiences between birth and death.
What strange thing has happened here? Well, what emerged in Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, this strongest unfolding of middle culture, in which the ego came to full consciousness, to inner experience, was only a reaction, a final reaction to something else. For one can only understand Kant if one correctly grasps the following. Now I come back to a concise point from which much can be derived. You see, Kant was still — as is clear from his earlier writings — a student of 18th-century rationalism, which found expression in Leibniz in a brilliant way and in Wolff in a pedantic way. And we can see that this rationalism was not really concerned with arriving at a spiritual reality—Kant therefore rejected this “thing in itself,” as he called it—but rather with proving, with proving with certainty! Kant's writings are also remarkable in this respect. He wrote his Critique of Pure Reason, in which he actually asks: How must the world be in order that we may prove things in it? Not: What are the realities involved? — but rather: How must I conceive of the world in order to be able to prove things in it logically and dialectically? — That is all that matters to him, and in his “Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science,” he seeks a metaphysics for what can be proven in his sense: Everything else is out! To hell with the reality of the world, just leave me the art of proof! What do I care what reality is; if I can't prove it, then I don't care about it!
Of course, those who wrote books such as Christian Wolff's “Reasonable Thoughts on God, the World, and the Human Soul, and on All Things in General” did not think in this way, but were concerned with having a clean, self-contained system of proofs, as they understood proof to be. Kant lived in this sphere; but there was at least something there that, although it was an exaggerated expression of the middle worldview, nevertheless fitted into the middle worldview. Kant, however, has something else that makes it inexplicable how he could become Fichte's teacher. He does, after all, inspire Fichte, and Fichte throws back at him the strong emphasis on “I am,” throwing back at him, however, not mere proofs, for one will not find those in Fichte, but a fully developed inner soul life. What emerges in Fichte with all the power of inner soul life is actually what can be found in a straw-like form in the Wolffians and Leibnizians. Fichte constructs his philosophy out of the “I am” in pure concepts; only in his case are they full of life. They are also found in Schelling and Hegel. But what actually happened there beyond Kant? Well, you come to the crux of the matter when you follow Kant's development. A student of Wolff's became something else because, as he himself says, the English philosopher David Hume woke him from his dull, apathetic slumber. What got into Kant that Fichte could no longer understand? Something entered Kant—it didn't fit him very well because he was too entangled in Central European culture—that is now Western culture. It confronted him in the personality of David Hume; Western culture entered Kant. And where can we find its distinctive features? In Eastern culture, we find that the ego still lives dimly, as if in a dream, in the experiences of the soul, which express themselves imaginatively and pictorially and spread out. In Western culture, we find that the Table 3
I am, as it were, crushed by purely external facts. The ego is present, but it is not present in a dull way; rather, it drills its way into the facts. And this gives rise to a strange psychology, for example. People do not talk about the life of the soul in the way that Fichte did, who wanted to work everything out from the single point of the ego; instead, they talk about thoughts and thoughts and thoughts, and these are associated with one another. One talks about feelings and ideas and sensations, and these associate with each other, and impulses of the will also associate with each other. One talks about the inner life of the soul as if it were thoughts that associate with each other.
Fichte talks about the ego; it radiates thoughts. In the West, the ego is completely absent because it is absorbed, soaked up by thoughts, by sensations that are made independent and that associate and separate again. And one pursues the life of the soul as if ideas were connecting and separating. Read Spencer, read John Stuart Mill, read the American philosophers: wherever they talk about psychology, there is this strange view that does not exclude the ego as in the Orient, because there it is developed in a dull way, but which makes full use of the ego, yet allows it to sink into the realm of the imagining, feeling, willing soul life. One could say that for Orientals, the ego is still above imagination, feeling, and willing; it has not yet descended to the level of imagination, feeling, and willing. In Western culture, the ego is already below the sphere, below the surface of thinking, feeling, and willing, so that at first it is no longer noticed and one speaks of thinking, feeling, and willing as if they were independent powers. This entered Kant in the form of David Hume's philosophy. The middle section of earthly culture opposed this with all its might in Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. Then, with Darwinism and Spencerism, Western culture flooded everything that was there at first.

Only then will it be possible to understand what lives in human development, if one investigates these deeper forces. Then one finds that something developed in the Orient in a natural way that was actually only spiritual life. In the middle region, something developed that was dialectical-legal, which actually gave rise to the idea of the state, because it is applicable to it. It is precisely thinkers such as Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel who construct unified state structures with tremendous sympathy. But then a culture emerges in the West that stems from a state of mind in which the ego is absorbed, functioning below the level of thinking, feeling, and willing, where one speaks of associations in the life of imagination and feeling. This way of thinking should only be applied to economic life! That is where it belongs. It was a complete mistake to apply it to anything other than economic life. There it is great, there it is brilliant, and if Spencer, John Stuart Mill, David Hume, if they had all applied what they wasted on philosophy to the institutions of economic life, it would have been magnificent. If the people living in Central Europe had limited what was their natural talent to the mere state, and if they had not at the same time wanted to grasp intellectual life and economic life, something great could have come of it. For with what Hegel was able to think, what Fichte was able to think, it would have been possible to achieve something magnificent if one had remained within the legal-state structure that we want to isolate in the threefold organism as the state structure. But because these minds had in mind that they had to create a state structure that included economic life and spiritual life, the result was caricatures instead of real state structures. And spiritual life was regarded as nothing more than a legacy of the ancient Orient. People simply did not realize that they were still living off this legacy of the ancient Orient. What are useful formulations of Christian theology, for example, or what are useful formulations even within our materialistic sciences, are either ancient Oriental heritage, or they are a changeling of legal-dialectical thinking, or they have already been taken over, as Spencer and Mill did, from Western culture, which is particularly suited to economic life.
Thus, the spiritual thinking of the ancient Orient was spread throughout the earth, but in an instinctive way that is no longer useful today, since it is now in decadence, dialectical-statistical thinking that experienced its dissolution precisely through the world catastrophe. For no one was less suited to economic thinking than the disciples of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. When they set out to found an empire that wanted to grow primarily through the economy, they were bound to fail, because that was not in their nature. According to the historical course of human development, spiritual thinking, state-political thinking, and economic thinking were distributed among the East, the Middle, and the West. We have reached the point in human development where understanding must spread throughout all of humanity, and understanding equally. How can this happen?
This can only happen through the culture of initiation, through the new spiritual science, which does not develop in a one-sided way, but which, in all areas, truly takes into account what has otherwise divided itself into three parts, as a threefold structure in social life, summarizing what is spread across the earth. However, this cannot be spread through natural predispositions; it can only be spread by engaging with those who see through these things, who can truly experience the spiritual realm as a special realm, the state or political realm as a special realm, and the economic realm as a special realm. This is where the unity of people across the Earth lies, in that what was distributed across three spheres is brought together in the human being, who structures it within the social organism in such a way that it can exist in harmony before him, before his very eyes. But this can only happen through spiritual scientific training. And here we come to the point where we have to say: We see the individual personalities of ancient times, we see them expressing what is the spirit of the age. But when we really examine this, for example within Oriental culture, we find that, basically, something of the soul state lived instinctively in the masses, which was in a remarkable, self-evident harmony with what the individuals expressed.
However, this interaction is becoming less and less. In our time, we see the opposite extreme emerging. We see the opposite instincts emerging in the masses, instincts that are actually harmful to humanity. We see emerging precisely what is necessary, what can flow out of the individual who is able to delve into the depths of spiritual science. Salvation will not come from instincts, but solely from the understanding that Dr. Unger has spoken of here, which is often emphasized, which every human being can bring to the spiritual researcher if they only truly surrender to common sense. Thus a culture will come in which the individuality of each person, with its ever deeper penetration into the inner depths of the spiritual worlds, will be of particular importance, and in which those who penetrate the spiritual worlds in this way will be accepted as equal to those who otherwise practice a craft. We don't have boots made by a tailor or our hair cut by a shoemaker, so why should we get what we need as a worldview from anyone other than those who are initiated into it? But this is precisely what is most urgently needed for the salvation of humanity at the present time, even though there is a reaction against it that shows how humanity is still resisting what is good for it. That is the terrible struggle, the seriousness in which we find ourselves.
Never has it been more necessary to listen to what individuals know in this or that field and to allow those who are knowledgeable in a particular area to influence social life, not on the basis of blind faith in authority, but on the basis of reason and understanding. But instincts initially oppose this, and people believe that something beneficial can be achieved through general levelling. That is the serious struggle in which we find ourselves. Sympathy and antipathy are of no help here, nor is a life lived by slogans; the only thing that helps is a clear view of the facts. For today, the big questions are being decided, the questions of whether the individual or the masses have any significance. In other times, this was not of great importance, because the masses were in harmony with the individual personalities; the personalities were, in a sense, only the exponents of the masses. We are increasingly moving toward a time when the individual must seek within himself the source of what he has to find and what he must then contribute to social life, and it is only the last resistance against this validity of individuality and an ever-increasing number of individualities. One can see clearly how what the spiritual sciences show is also proven everywhere at the crucial point. We speak of the necessary associations in economic life, and we need a certain way of thinking to do this. In Western culture, this has developed by allowing thoughts to associate with each other. If one could take what John Stuart Mill does with logic, if one could take these thoughts out of there and apply them to economic life, they would fit in, and the associations that do not fit into psychology would come in. Spiritual science pursues reality right down to what appears in the realm of human development.
Therefore, spiritual science stands with full awareness in the midst of the seriousness of the present world situation. It knows what a great struggle is taking place between what can come out of spiritual science in the form of social impulses in the threefold social order and what is opposing this threefold social order in the form of a Bolshevik wave that would lead to the ruin of humanity. And there is no third option between these two. The struggle must take place between these two. This must be understood. Everything else is already decadent. Anyone who looks impartially at the circumstances in which we find ourselves must admit that it is necessary today to gather all our forces so that this terrible Ahrimanic force, which opposes spiritual culture, can be repelled.
This building stands there, unfinished for the time being. Today, the central countries do not have what has brought it to this point, in connection with what has come to us from the neutral states. We must have subsidies from the countries of the former Entente. Understanding must be developed for what is to become a unified culture that encompasses spirit, politics, and economics. For people must move away from a one-sided mindset and follow those who also understand politics and economics, who do not merely engage in dialectics but also see through intellectual matters and are open to economic stimuli, who do not want to found states in which the state itself can already manage the economy. The Western peoples will have to realize that their special gift for the future in economic association, which they have applied in exactly the wrong place, in psychology, must develop into a full understanding of the state-political element, which has sources other than economic life, and of the spiritual element. But the central countries are lying on the ground. People in Western regions will have to realize what this structure here is trying to achieve—the Orient is out of the question! It is therefore necessary to reflect on how to ensure that the culture that now wants to manifest itself here as a culture that is called upon to permeate the higher education of the future, and which has shown itself in the founding of the Waldorf School as one that can illuminate the elementary school system, is truly provided for. But to do this, we need the understanding support of the widest possible circles.
Above all, we need resources. For everything that school means in the higher or lower sense, we need the attitude that I already expressed when the Waldorf School was founded in Stuttgart; I said it in my opening speech at the founding: This one Waldorf school, yes, it's wonderful that we have it, but it is nothing in itself; it will only be something if we establish ten more Waldorf schools in the next quarter of a year, and then more. The world did not understand this; it had no money for it. For it stands at the point of view: Oh, the ideals are too high and too pure for us to bring dirty money to them; we'd rather keep it in our pockets, where it belongs, dirty money. The ideals, oh, they are far too pure to be sullied with money! However, it is not possible to achieve such an embodiment of ideals with the purity that dirty money cannot bring, and so we must remember that we have so far remained with one Waldorf school, which cannot really move forward because we were in great financial difficulties in the fall. These have been resolved for the time being; at Easter we will be back where we started. And here, here we will ask ourselves after a relatively short time: Should we stop? And we will have to stop if we do not find a very deep understanding that reaches into people's pockets.
That is why it is important to awaken understanding in this direction. I do not believe that much understanding would arise—we have already seen this—if we were to say that we want something for the building in Dornach or something similar. But—and this is still understood today—if you want to establish sanatoriums or something similar, you can get as much money as you want! That is not exactly what we want; we do not want to establish sanatoriums, although we fully agree with their establishment insofar as they are necessary. Here, however, it is primarily a matter of cultivating the spiritual culture whose necessity will be proven by what this university course here has sought to achieve. That is why I tried to suggest what I summarized here a few days ago: a “world school association.” Our German friends have left; they are not important for this world school association. What matters is that those who have come here as friends, mostly from all parts of the non-German world, and who are still sitting here, understand this term “World School Association,” for it is necessary that we establish schools upon schools in all parts of the world based on the pedagogical and didactic spirit that prevails in the Waldorf School. It is necessary that we be able to expand this school until we find a connection to what we want here as a system of higher education. To do this, however, it is necessary that we are able to complete this building with everything that belongs to it and that we can continually maintain what is necessary to work here, to create, to create the further development of all the individual sciences out of the spirit of spiritual science.
People ask how much money is needed for all this. It is impossible to say how much is needed, because there is no upper limit. Of course, we will not establish a world school association by creating a committee of twelve or fifteen or thirty people who draw up beautiful statutes on how such a world school association should function and work. That is all pointless. I do not care about programs or statutes, but about the work of living people who act with understanding. One day it will be possible to found this world school association; well, it will be a long time before we can come to London, but from The Hague or a place like that, if a foundation is laid in this way, and through many other things, if those friends who are now going to Norway or Sweden or Holland or to any other country, to England, France, America, and so on, if these friends everywhere, every person they can reach, the conviction, the well-founded conviction: There must be a World School Association! — That would spread like wildfire throughout the world: A World School Association must be established to procure the material means for the spiritual culture that is meant here. - If one can convince hundreds and hundreds of people of all kinds of things as an individual, why should one not be able to influence many people in a short time — for decline is so rapid that we have only a short time at our disposal — so that when one comes to The Hague after a few weeks, one would see how widespread the conviction already is: The establishment of a World School Association is necessary, only the means to achieve this are lacking. What is wanted from Dornach is a historical necessity. Then we will be able to talk about the inauguration of this World School Association when the opinion about it is already there. To establish committees and decide on a world school association is utopian and serves no purpose; but to work from person to person and to spread the opinion, the well-founded opinion, with the speed that is necessary, is what must precede the foundation. Spiritual science lives in realities. That is why it does not engage in programmatic attempts at founding, but points to what must happen among realities—for human beings are reality—among human beings, so that such a thing has a chance of success.
So what matters is that we finally learn from spiritual science to stand in real life. I will never engage in a merely utopian justification of the World School Association, but I will always be of the opinion that the World School Association can only come into being when a sufficiently large number of people are convinced of its necessity. And in order that what is necessary for humanity — as has been proven in our university courses — can happen, this World School Association must be founded. So let us see what is meant by this World School Association in the right sense in the whole of international life! With this appeal, I would like to conclude today with what has been said to humanity in a completely different way throughout our entire course, precisely by those who have been here and whom we hope and wish will carry it out into the world. The World School Association can be the world's answer to what is being posed as a question, but a question that is taken from the real forces of human development, that is, from human history. So, what can happen for the World School Association according to the conviction you have gained here over the last three weeks, let it happen! This echoes what I still wanted to say today.