Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

Search results 11 through 20 of 433

˂ 1 2 3 4 5 6 ... 44 ˃
6. Goethe's World View: The Consequences of the Platonic World View
Tr. William Lindemann

Rudolf Steiner
Mistrust toward the world of perception is also present in Kant. To these habits of thinking there is added the influence of Hume. Kant agrees with Hume with respect to his assertion that the ideas into which thinking combines the individual perceptions do not stem from experience, but rather that thinking adds them to experience.
Kant, however, renounces the notion that ideas open any real insight into the being of the world, just so they retain the quality of the eternal and necessary.
[ 7 ] Kant's philosophical way of picturing things was in addition particularly nourished by the direction of his religious feelings.
2. The Science of Knowing: Intellect and Reason
Tr. William Lindemann

Rudolf Steiner
But this does not apply to ideas themselves. For Kant these do not have even this degree of objectivity. [ 21 ] Kant finds that the principles of mathematics and of pure natural science are such valid synthetical principles a priori.
In \(7\) and \(5\) the sum \(12\) is in no way contained, concludes Kant. I must go beyond \(7\) and \(5\) and call upon my intuition; 1 then I find the concept \(12\).
Anschauung—“Intuition” is the conventional translation of Kant's Anschauang.—Ed.
76. The Stimulating Effect of Anthroposophy on the Individual Sciences: Philosophy 04 Apr 1921, Dornach

Rudolf Steiner
And basically, what then emerged in Kantian philosophy is nothing other than, I would say, the last consequence of this scholastic problem. It is just that Kant arrived at his formulation of the scholastic problem in a peculiar way: in the age in which Kant, as a young man, was pursuing his philosophical studies, a somewhat diluted Leibnizianism prevailed in the circles in which Kant was pursuing his studies.
There must be certainty in philosophy. That was one side of what Kant wanted. And anyone who does not grasp how firmly Kant stood on the ground: there must be certainty — also in the sense of Wolffian philosophy — does not understand Kant, because he cannot engage with Kant's insistence on the certainty of certain judgments.
And finally, if we consider the historical, we can say that a great deal has been worked out positively from Kant. There are not only the critical Kant philologists, not only the neo-Kantians of the likes of Liebmann, Volkelt and so on, but there is the very active Marburg School – Cohen, Cassirer, Dilthey and so on – which tried to work out the positive from Kant in a certain sense.
2. A Theory of Knowledge: Intellect and Reason
Tr. Olin D. Wannamaker

Rudolf Steiner
Kant, therefore, designated ideas, not as constitutive principles which must be determinative for things, but as regulative principles which have meaning and significance only for the systematics of our knowledge.
But this principle cannot be applied to ideas themselves. According to Kant these never possess that degree of objectivity. [ 21 ] Kant decides that the propositions of mathematics and pure natural science are a priori such valid propositions.
The same is true of the geometrical examples cited by Kant. A limited straight line with the termini A and B is an indivisible unit. My intellect can form two concepts of this.
7. Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern Age: Preface to the First Edition, 1901
Tr. Karl E. Zimmer

Rudolf Steiner
For now a benevolent critic gave the following advice: “Before he continues to reform and brings his Philosophy of Spiritual Activity into the world, one must urgently advise him first to penetrate to an understanding of those two philosophers (Hume and Kant).” The critic unfortunately knows only what he can manage to read in Kant and Hume; thus he really only advises me to see nothing in these thinkers beyond what he sees.
—Especially diverting for me was the advice of a man who is so impressed by the way he “understands” Kant that he cannot even imagine someone's having read Kant and nevertheless having an opinion different from his. He therefore indicates to me the chapters in question in Kant's writings from which I might acquire an under standing of Kant as profound as his own. [ 4 ] I have here adduced a few typical judgments concerning my world of ideas.
31. Collected Essays on Cultural and Contemporary History 1887–1901: Haeckel Tolstoy and Nietzsche 09 Nov 1901,

Rudolf Steiner
Then Kant came along and declared that man was not at all predisposed to recognize the real nature of things. Kant betrayed the deepest impulses of his thinking when he wrote the words: "I therefore had to destroy knowledge in order to make room for faith." In Kant's opinion, this knowledge is only limited; it can never penetrate to where the objects of faith, God, freedom and immortality, have their domain.
51. Schiller and Our Times: Schiller's Work and its Changing Transformations 28 Jan 1905, Berlin
Tr. Harry Collison

Rudolf Steiner
In his Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Practical Reason Kant had set a definite limit to human knowledge. Man's capacity for knowledge extends as far as reason goes.
Thus Schiller reaches the heights and rises above Kant. He opposes Kant who makes of man not a free being but a slave, bowed beneath the yoke of duty. He saw clearly that there is something in man quite different from this bowing beneath the yoke of the “Thou shalt.”
Kant apostrophises passionately the stern duty which has nothing attractive in her. Schiller raises man from his own weakness, when he makes the moral law a law of his own nature.
51. The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity (1963): Introduction

Hugo S. Bergman
Goethe's understanding of nature brought him in opposition to Kant. The problem here is the limitation of our knowledge. In this difference of views, Steiner in his interpretation of Goethe took the side of the latter, in opposition to Kant, and thus put himself in opposition to the Neo-Kantians, whose views were taught in all German universities at that time.
This fundamentally new principle, however, is by no means something of a subjective nature which, according to Kant, man projects on the given perception, or on nature, but rather the true essence of the world of the senses itself.
In this way Steiner has succeeded in building up a truly objective idealism, from Kant back to Plato, or forward to Schelling. What is new in Kant's philosophy—his idealism in contrast to dogmatism—remains in Steiner's world conception.
52. Epistemological Foundation of Theosophy III 17 Dec 1903, Berlin

Rudolf Steiner
In the preceding talks I have tried to outline the basic thoughts of the present theory of knowledge, as it is done at our universities, and as it is also done by those philosophers and thinking researchers who lean upon Schopenhauer, Kant and similar great German thinkers. I tried to show at the same time how the whole scientific development of the 19th century, whether the physical one, the physiological one and also the psychological one, accepted Kant’s epistemology or those forms of it which Schopenhauer or Eduard von Hartmann created.
If I am completely within my thinking, then it is impossible as it is impossible for the thinking of the adherents of Kant and Schopenhauer. Imagine Kant sitting at his desk and judging only from himself. It is not possible to get an objective judgment this way.
If it is certain that the world is spirit in its being, we can fully position ourselves on the standpoint which Kant and Schopenhauer take. All that is correct, but it does not go far enough. It is easy to adapt to Kant and Schopenhauer.
2. A Theory of Knowledge: Goethe's Science Considered According to the Method of Schiller
Tr. Olin D. Wannamaker

Rudolf Steiner
Where similar inquiries appear nowadays, they almost invariably take Kant as their point of departure. It has been altogether overlooked in scientific circles that, beside the science of knowledge set up by the great thinker of Königsberg, there is at least the possibility of another trend of thought in this field, no less capable than that of Kant of dealing profoundly with the facts. [ 6 ] Otto Liebmann at the beginning of the 'sixties gave expression to the conviction that we must return to Kant if we would attain to a view of the world free of contradictions. This is the reason why we possess to-day a Kant literature almost beyond the possibility of survey. But this road also will fail to afford any assistance to philosophical thinking, which will not again play a role in our cultural life until, instead of returning to Kant, it enters more deeply into the scientific conceptions of Goethe and Schiller. [ 7 ] And now we shall touch upon one of the basic questions of a science of knowledge corresponding to these preliminary remarks.

Results 11 through 20 of 433

˂ 1 2 3 4 5 6 ... 44 ˃